Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and Religions.
Vol 1 No 1 ISSN: 2276-8386 (Print) E-ISSN: 2408-5987 2021
Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and Religions. Vol 3 No 2
FILOSOFIA THEORETICA
JOURNAL OF AFRICAN PHILOSOPHY,
CULTURE AND RELIGIONS
A Publication of
The Calabar School of Philosophy (CSP)
Department of Philosophy, University of Calabar
www.csp.unical.edu.ng
SPECIAL ISSUE:
POSTMODERNISM AND AFRICAN PHILOSOPHY
VOLUME 3 NUMBER 2 JULY-DECEMBER, 2014
ISSN: 2276-8386 (Print)
E-ISSN: 2408-5987 (Online)
http://www.ajol.info/index.php/ft/index
ISBN: 978-150-58521-5-8
Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and Religions
FILOSOFIA THEORETICA
JOURNAL OF AFRICAN PHILOSOPHY,
CULTURE AND RELIGIONS
The Calabar School of Philosophy (CSP)
Department of Philosophy, University of Calabar
PHILOSOPHY
DECEMBER, 2014
(Online)
http://www.ajol.info/index.php/ft/index
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
Editorial Board
Dr. Jonathan O. Chimakonam
Dr. Mesembe I. Edet
Dr. Mulumba Obiajulu
Sunny Nzie Agu
Dr. Oduora O. Asuo
Lucky U. Ogbonnaya
Victor Nweke
Aniyom Grace
Segun Samuel
Editorial Consultants
Professor Innocent Asouzu
Professor Andrew Uduigwomen
Professor Udobata Onunwa
Professor Godfrey Ozumba
Professor Oladele Balogun
Professor Udo Etuk
Professor Apollos Nwauwa
Professor Olatunji Oyeshile
Professor Dorothy Olu-Jacob
Prof. Uduma O. Uduma
Professor Fainos Mangena
Page2
Page2
Editor-in- Chief
Assoc. Editor
Managing Editor
Secretary
Member
Editorial Assistant
Editorial Assistant
Computer/Typeset
Graphics
University of Calabar
University of Calabar
University of Birmingham UK
University of Calabar
Olabisi Olabanjo University
University of Uyo
Bowling Green State University
University of Ibadan
University of Calabar
Ebonyi State University
University of Zimbabwe
Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and
Religions is a publication of the Calabar School of Philosophy. It
publishes twice each year, January-June and July-December.
Manuscripts are to be submitted electronically to
filosofiatheoretica@unical.edu.ng
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
Note to Contributors:
General Information: Filosofia Theoretica Journal of African Philosophy, Culture
and Religions is dedicated to the promotion of conversational orientation and
publication of astute academic research in African Philosophy, Culture, History,
Art, Literature, Science, Education and Religions, etc. The articles submitted to
Filosofia Theoretica must be presented in defensive style i.e. defending or
promoting some theses and review of books are also covered within the standard
range of this journal. The journal has a vision to put Africa and African
intellectuals on the global map. However, this does not imply that non-Africans
cannot submit articles for consideration insofar as the title fall within the focus of
the journal.
Submission Requirements: All manuscripts must be original (hence, not under
consideration anywhere) and submitted to the editor in MS word format via e
mail: filosofiatheoretica@unical.edu.ng
. The entire work can range from 2000 to
6000 words maximum excluding citations with a concise title and a 150 word
abstract. Authors are not to place page numbers or paper title (on each page) on
the manuscript; we no longer accept endnotes and footnotes. Articles (or parts of
articles) in languages other than English will no longer be considered. All
submissions must list the author's current affiliation and contact points (location,
e-mail address, etc.). In regards to style the Calabar School of Philosophy
Documentation Style which is downloadable from the journal’s site is the only
acceptable reference style. Camera ready manuscripts will receive first
preference in the publishing cycle. Any manuscript not well proof read will not
be considered for review. All manuscripts are peer-reviewed and those
considered acceptable by the editors will be published after recommended
corrections free of any charges as quality and originality are the ONLY
conditions for publishing essays in this journal.
Aim:
FILOSOFIA THEORETICA was founded by Jonathan O. Chimakonam in May
2010 and the aim is to make it a world class academic journal with a global brand
that would thrive on standard, quality and originality, promoting and sustaining
conversational orientation in African Philosophy. It is published twice a year
with maximum of ten (10) articles including book review on each volume in both
print and online editions with separate ISSN. The Online version is published by
Ajol, South Africa.
Page3
Page3
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
Review Process:
Generally, Editors should be able to reach a decision including recommending
corrections if any or acceptance of any paper within three months of receipt
which is communicated to the author subsequently. Authors are therefore advised
to avoid needless correspondences. Also, Editors are not committed to the views
expressed in articles. Contributors may receive one copy of the journal free of
charge but additional copies may be obtained at the normal price. Copyright to
articles published in the journal shall remain vested with the journal. All
correspondences including subscription, copyright and sponsorship to the Editor
via: filosofiatheoretica@gmail.com
www.csp.unical.edu.ng
or csp.info@unical.edu.ng
, www.africanphilcongress.com
, or at:
http://www.ajol.info/index.php/ft/index
http://www.worldcat.org/oclc/813461588
Indexing Information:
Visit us at:
Filosofia Theoretica is indexed by many depositories such as Ajol, Google
Scholar, OCLC Worldcat, Archive.org, Scribd, Academia.edu, AfricaBib,
Stanford.edu, etc. This makes essays published in the journal widely accessible.
Contact:
C/O, Editor
Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy,
Culture and Religions,
The Calabar School of Philosophy,
Department of Philosophy,
University of Calabar,
Calabar.
PO BOX 3684, Cross River State,
Nigeria.
Telephone: +234-7035254923
E-mail: csp.info@unical.edu.ng
Page4
Page4
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
Editorial
Our readers who have read the previous issues of this journal know exactly what
to expect in this Volume 3 Number 2. Like we always say, Filosofia Theoretica
has emerged as one of the vocal outlets for rigorous essays on African
philosophy and sundry fields. Now, we encourage contemporary African
philosophers to engage in critical discussions aimed at building an architectonic
individual-based episteme for African philosophy in keeping with our founding
principle of promoting and sustaining conversational African philosophy. This
special issue is dedicated to the theme of postmodernism where African
philosophy is presented as a postmodern resistance to the hegemony of Western
philosophy.
To this end, Joseph Agbo writing from Ebonyi State University explored
some nagging issues on the post-modern scientific thoughts of Thomas Kuhn and
Paul Feyerabend taking special interest on their Implications for Africa. For those
hoping to see the foot-prints of postmodernism on African thought and a lucid
textual interpretation of Kuhn and Feyerabend,, this essay is a must read.
And from Obafemi Awolowo University Ile-Ife, Jacob Adetolu writes on
the subject of Religion, Postmodernism and Postmodern Scholarship in Africa.
This essay makes a stunning reading on the appraisal of postmodernism in a
broader sense and specifically in the area of postmodern scholarship in the
discipline of religious studies in Africa. This essay is critical, prescriptive and
novel most of all.
Writing from the University of Nigeria, Nsukka Dr.Augustine Atabor
discusses the question of objectivity, its implications for the social sciences in the
era of postmodernism and in particular, from an African perspective. Those who
know the importance of objectivity in any philosophical discourse would relish
the idea of an African philosophy perspective to it.
Also from the Obafemi Awolowo University Ile-Ife writes David
Oyedola on The Culture-oriented Bias of African Philosophical Inquiry. Does
culture merely influence a philosophy or is culture philosophy? What sort of
influence has African culture on African philosophy? Questions like these inform
the critical investigations carried out by the author in this deeply incisive essay.
Those who cherish surprising and unexpected insights would love this essay.
Page5
Page5
Coming from the Federal University Lafia, Dr. Isaiah Negedu writes on
the Scientific Progress and Postmodern Culture: The African Experience. This
scintillating essay welds the radicalism of postmodernism and the dynamism of
African thought in one piece of adorable writing. Any serious scholar would love
to read this essay.
Dr. Jonathan Chimakonam writing from the University of Calabar
dwells on the curious subject of Ududo Reasoning in African Thought as a
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
Postmodern Formalist Method in Logic. All logic freaks and indeed, every
scholar who love to read original thoughts would find this essay quite
compelling.
Also from the University of Calabar writes Segun Samuel writes on the
controversial Prefix “African” and its Implication for Philosophy in Africa. All
those who enjoy the writing style of the greats like Peter Bodunrin would love
this essay. Segun unleashes his arguments with rare candor that makes for joyous
reading.
And from far away University of Zimbabwe, Prof. Fainos Mangena
inquires: Can Africana Women truly embrace Ecological Feminism? Those who
are keen on the subject of feminism and the debates on environmental philosophy
and Africana agitations cannot afford not to read this new and fresh perspective.
And finally from the Erasmus University Netherlands, Prof. Heinz
Kimmerle sends in his review of Sophie Oluwole’s mind-bugling book on
Socrates and Orunmila: Two Patron Saints of Classical Philosophy, first
published by the German-based Journal Confluence (2014). To the duo of
Kimmerle and the editorial management of Confluence, we owe enormous
gratitude for granting us the permission to reprint this scintillating review here.
Those who wish to read a great summary of the book on the great Greek thinker
Socrates and the Great Yoruba thinker Orunmila would have Kimmerle to thank.
Oluwole’s book is curious; the review of it by Kimmerle is superb.
As this is a Special Issue of Filosofia Theoretica focusing on
Postmodernisn and African Philosophy, we enjoin African and scholars in
African thought to freely send in their comments or discussions on any of the
essays in this issue for publication in a subsequent issue. Comments and
discussions should not exceed 750 words on a 12 point time new roman. We are
glad to serve you once again this intellectual menu. An anonymous African
thinker once said that if the agama lizard fell from the top of iroko and no one
praised him, he will nod his head and praise himself. We praise our contributors
who are the real heroes ceaselessly penning down essays that promote and
sustain conversational African philosophy. Hakuna Matata!
Editor -in- Chief
Page6
Page6
Vol. 3 No. 2 July – December, 2014
Page7 Page7
CONTENTS
Editorial 5-6
The Post-Modern Scientific Thoughts of Thomas Kuhn and Paul
Feyerabend: Implications for Africa
Joseph N. AGBO 9-37
Religion, Postmodernism and Postmodern Scholarship in Africa
Jacob O. ADETOLU 38-49
The Question of Objectivity, its Implications for the Social Sciences in the
Era of Postmodernism: Africa in Perspective
Augustine A. ATABOR 50-61
The Culture-oriented Bias of African Philosophical Inquiry
David A. OYEDOLA 62-80
Scientific Progress and Postmodern Culture: The African Experience
Isaiah NEGEDU 81-89
Ududo Reasoning in African Thought: A Postmodern Formalist Method for
Logic
Jonathan O. CHIMAKONAM 90-105
The Prefix “African” and its Implication for Philosophy in Africa
Samuel T. SEGUN 106-123
Can Africana Women truly embrace Ecological Feminism?
Fainos MANGENA 124-139
An Amazing Piece of Comparative Philosophy
Heinz KIMMERLE 140-142
Vol. 3 No. 2 July – December, 2014
Page8 Page8
Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and Religions
THE POST-MODERN SCIENTIFIC THOUGHTS OF THOMAS KUHN
AND PAUL FEYERABEND: IMPLICATIONS FOR AFRICA
Joseph N. AGBO
Senior Lecturer, Department of Philosophy,
Ebonyi State University, Abakaliki, Nigeria.
Abstract
Postmodernism is like a spectre hunting the intellectual world, and there is a
sense in which the attitude is, first and foremost, against modern science. This
essay is, therefore, an expository analysis of the thoughts of Thomas Kuhn and
Paul Feyerabend, as classical representations of the postmodern reaction against
modern science. The paper argues that the colossal image of science, as well as
the idea of a “unity of sciences” had to be jettisoned by postmodernism in order
to make way for the relativism and multiplicity of points of view that are
symptomatic of postmodern thinking. The paper concludes with some critical
reflections of the thoughts of the two scholars, and notes that postmodernism
opened the door for the recognition of African ideas and ideals. The implication
is that postmodernism not only vitiates the hold exercised by Western European
models of reality but equally gives fresh cultural confidence to other modes of
cognition, especially in Africa, that have long been pushed to the periphery.
Keywords: Modernity, Postmodernity, Transmodernity, Science, Paradigm,
Pluri-versality, Incommensurability.
Introduction
It does appear, and there are cogent reasons for it, that one does not need to be
neck deep in logical rigor to argue that there is a sense in which postmodernism
is first and foremost a reaction against science; that is, modern science.
Understanding the background to and of modernity as well as grasping the core
of postmodern thinking, would be enough to let any minimally intelligent person
know that the claims of modernity are science-anchored; and consequently, one
cannot attack modernity “postmodernly”, without at the same time (and
simultaneously) attacking science.
When modernity became referred to as the “Age of Reason”, it was not
an attempt to aver that the periods before it (the ancient and medieval periods, for
example) were characterized by “un-Reason” or that “Reason” was, as it were,
given birth to during the modern period. No! The Reason in question is the
Reason of Rationality, or better stated, logical consistency. In W.H. Newton
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
Smith’s lucid and popular book, [The Rationality of Science], he states that
science and the scientific community “is taken to be in possession of something,
the scientific method, which generates a logic of justification (1). He goes on to
aver that at the majestic dawn of modern science, it became the very “paradigm
of institutionalized rationality” (1).
This essay argues not only that postmodernism represents a heavy
reaction against science, but goes on to unveil the thoughts of Thomas Kuhn and
Paul Feyerabend as typologies or classic representation of the postmodern
attitude in science. After this introduction, we shall, for the purpose of those who
may not be very familiar with the concept, briefly capture the meaning and basic
tenets of postmodernism. We would then proceed by exploring what
postmodernism had to do to modern science, in order to pave the way for the
postmodern conception of science.
Having done the foregoing, we shall then proceed to do an exposition of
the thoughts of Kuhn and Feyerabend as examples of the kind of things that
postmodernists are saying about science. Although the scholars are not saying the
same things (well, no one should expect them to) if we understand the kernel of
postmodernism, we would discover that the authors all arrive at the
postmodernism shores, eventually, from different departure harbors. After all,
postmodernism is not really a school of thought but an attitude to and of
philosophizing.
Showing the meaning of postmodernism and its root in modern science
and the “how” and “why” the thoughts of Kuhn and Feyerabend are [postmodern
scientific attitudes, and how this attitude pluralized the conceptions of reality to
the advantage of Africa’s modes of cognitions, would be the modest purpose of
this essay. Gleaning postmodernism from Kuhn and Feyerabend would be
interesting because since postmodernism is an attitude, many postmodernists do
not even know that they are. We would, however, end this essay with some
critical comments on both the positions of Kuhn and Feyerabend noting briefly
some implications for Africa, as well as on the project of postmodernism as a
whole.
Page10
After all, one of the most crucial challenges faced in the attempts to
present African thought system or articulate Africa’s conceptions of reality was
the accusation that they were “unscientific” (science as modern science).
Rationality was ultimately interpreted in Western European terms, with modern
science as its legitimate heralder and accredited distributor. And so any view or
theory that would not just for the purpose of arguments, but as a matter of fact,
debunk the colossal and gargantuan image of modern science should necessarily
be of interest to Africa. For it would be the dawn of epistemological and
ontological freedom.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
A Brief on Postmodernism
Anyone familiar with postmodernism knows that it is sometimes easier to say
what postmodernism is NOT than what it IS. In other words, it would be simpler
to say what a postmodernist rejects than what he accepts. What this section
would do is to provide a brief information on what postmodernism is, in order to
give the reader a key into the scientific thoughts of Kuhn and Feyerabend.
To understand the “postmodern”, one needs to understand the “modern”;
for what postmodernism rejects are all that makes modernism tick. The “post” in
postmodernism has been given two interpretations. While some see it as “anti”,
others perceive it as “beyond” or “after” modernity. In his paper,
“Postmodernism is Existentialist Phenomenology” Jim I. Unah argues that to
conceive postmodernism as just anti-modernity is to betray a truncated
understanding of what it is and indeed should be. For him, this limited
conception is tantamount to saying the “mainstream Kierkegaardean
Existentialism had only the task of combating the ‘system’ and its principal
expositor—the professor” (114). For him, postmodernism is “beyond
modernity”; that is, an improvement on, not opposition to, modernity.
Page11
To be candid, unless we discuss postmodernism in an “unpostmodern”
way, we may get stuck with dumbness at worst, and intelligibility at best. This is
because discussing postmodernism in a historical or chronological way is not
useful, for according to William Spanos, in his “De-struction and the Question of
Postmodern Literature: Towards a Definition”, Postmodernism is not a
chronological event, but a permanent mode of human understanding” (107). For
how does one begin to grapple with a term whose proponents even abhor
definitions? In his edited book, [The Cambridge Companion to Postmodern
Theology], Kevin J. Vanhoozer writes that, those who try to define or even
analyze the concept of post modernity usually do so at their own peril; in the first
place, no definition is neutral and, secondly, definitions give “totalizing”
accounts. Consequently, in Vanhoozer’s understanding of what the
postmodernists are saying, “a definition of postmodernity is as likely to say more
about the person offering the definition than it is of ‘the postmodern’” (1).
Unfortunately, while those who agree that they are postmodernists are not in
agreement as to what it is they are, some of those whose thoughts tilt towards the
postmodern reject the term. Is it any wonder then that in his book, [The Idea of a
Postmodern: A History], Hans Bertens comments that the term “postmodernism”
and other terms derived from it, such as “postmodern”, “postmodernity”,
“postmodernize”, “postmoderrnist”, “are not only exasperating, but equally
confusing and compounding” (3).
In his essay “Process Thought and Harmony”, Warayuth Sriwara Kuel says
that despite the ambiguous and multiple meaning of the word “postmodern”, the
term has become a “specter” roaming around the academic world, since “more
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
and more intellectuals from various fields like to use the word to label their ideas
and positions” (101). However, for Lawrence E. Cahoone, in [From Modernism
to Postmodernism: An Anthology] gives 3 main connotations that philosophical
reflections on postmodernism revolves around, and then argues, in my opinion,
falsely that “all three reactions are misguided. Certainly the term ‘postmodern’…
can be subjected to easy riddicle as hopelessly ambiguous and empty” (1). The 3
connotations of postmodernism identified by Cahoone are: one, it refers to the
last escape from authoritarianism, colonialism, racism and domination which are
all legacies of modern European thought; two, it connotes the attempt by
intellectuals on the Left to destroy Western Civilization; and three, a collection of
hermeneutic writers and scholars whose obscure presentations make it look as
though they are not saying anything. What is significant, for us Africa, the
Cahoone’s classification is that the first one appears to be the major goal of
postmodernism- an escape by those that have long been on the periphery of
Western intellectual domination. If postmodernism is concerned as a “going
beyondness” hardly will it be of interest to us as Africans. The second
characterization appears to be a reaction by Western intellectuals to paint
postmodernism in bad light. And on the fact that some postmodernists appear
obscure, I think it is part of the protest character of postmodernism itself- it is a
reaction against the simple and naïve progressiveness of modernity
Page12
I do not think, however, that we should get trapped or lost in the labyrinth of
the excessive and polemical “scholarshipism” of postmodernism. For if
postmodernists disagree about many things, they would never disagree on the
fact that postmodernism is a rejection of absolutes, essences and foundations.
Jean Francios Lyotard, one of the contemporary proponents of postmodernism
captures its meaning succinctly when he says in [The Postmodern Condition],
that postmodernism is “incredulity towards metanaratives” (109 ). By this, he
means that we should abandon all attempts we make to find a grand, universal,
trans-historical, transcultural scheme, paradigm or algorithm with which we can
legitimize knowledge or justify the choice of one theory over another. Having
abandoned the search for a grand norm, we are then left with heterogeneous,
pluralistic multiplicity, incommensurable differences. No wonder James Morley,
(UNAH 117) opines, as a corollary, that postmodernists “see the dissolutions of
distinction, the merging of subject and object, self and other… a sarcastic playful
parody of Western modernity and a radical anarchist rejection of all attempts to
define reality or re-present the human subject”. Postmodernism rejects the
essential pillars of the modern period: Reason (Rationality) and Method
(Science). In his [Multicultural Citizenship], Will Kymlicka writes about “the
debate between…rationalists and postmodernists” (153), thereby juxtaposing
postmodernism and rationalism.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
Post-modernism, therefore, is a calculated and frontal rejection of the various
rationalist and modernist, models of interpretation of reality, especially those
ideas that lay tenacious grip on the immutability of knowledge, truth and
essentialism. Post-modernism sees reality as a social construct, given meaning
only within the context of certain defined cultural conditions. For them any
reality not defined and characterized by communities or societies, based on their
cultural particularity, is no reality at all. Consequently, post-modernism rejects
all ideas and theories that lay claim or essay to be cross-cultural; such as
Marxism, Humanism, Existentialism, Socialism, Essentialism, Darwinism,
Creationism, Evolutionism, Spiritualism, Religionism, etc. These theories are
regarded as being authoritative and possessive of absolute truth, and therefore,
unable to access reality.
Writing in an essay titled, “Richard Rorty and the Postmodern Rejection
of Absolute Truth”, Dean Geuras quotes Rorty (Geuras calls Him
“postmodernism’s most-gifted defender”) as saying that there is no “Skyhook”
which removes us from our subjective condition to reveal any reality existing
independent of our perception. Recall that in his earlier book [Philosophy and the
Mirror of Nature], Rorty had laid the blame of the “evils” of the modern period
on Kantian Foundationalism, and argues in chapter 3 “The Idea of a ‘Theory of
Knowledge’’ that it was this attempt to “Theorize” on knowledge that created the
castrating hegemony of modern epistemology, to which postmodern
hermeneutics stands opposed. For Rorty, therefore:
Hermeneutics is an expression of hope that the cultural space left by the
demise of epistemology will not be filled, that our culture should
become one in which the demand for constraint and confrontation is no
longer felt. The notion that there is a permanent neutral framework
whose “structure” philosophy can display is the notion that the objects
to be confronted by the mind, or rules which constrain enquiry, are
common to all discourse, or at least to every discourse on a given topic.
Thus epistemology proceeds on the assumption that all contributions to
a given discourse are commensurable. Hermeneutics is largely a
struggle against this assumption. (315-316)
Page13
The ambivalence between epistemology and hermeneutics is not strictly our
concern here. I have addressed it more closely in my essay, “Science and the
‘End’ of Epistemology”. But our interest is on the fact that the postmodernists
see the modern period as the dawn of Reason and Science, and the grand
theorizing led to, as the [Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy] puts it, “a naive and
earnest confidence in progress… in objective and scientific truth”, the result is
that postmodernism became, in philosophy, “a mistrust for the grand’s recites of
modernity, the large scale justifications of Western society and confidence in its
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
progress visible in Kant, Hegel or Marx or arising from ‘utopian’ visions of
perfection achieved through evolution, social improvements, education, or the
deployment of science”(294-5).
A mere cursory glance at postmodernism would reveal that it does appear
that if modernity would survive, if one could still hoist what James F. Harris, in
his challenging book, [Against Relativism: A Philosophical Defense of Method],
“the tattered flag of modernity” (4), then we must save modern science and the
epistemological foundation that stands at its philosophical base. Otherwise, the
collapse of science marks the collapse of the Modern Enlightenment project. But
that’s not the fundamental desire of postmodernists. They want to, as Rorty puts
it, open “cultural space” to multiple and plural criteria of justification and
legitimization. At this point, we must move on.
Postmodernism and Modern Science
I must observe from the onset that before what we come to know as modern
science, whatever was baptized “scientific” or “science” was mainly developed
from the philosophy of the encyclopedic-minded Greek philosopher, Aristotle.
Most of what later became the concerns of Astronomy were based on Aristotle’s
musings on theories. As a matter of fact Claudius Ptolemy’s geocentric
conception of the universe (that the Earth was the centre of the solar system, and
all other planets; including the Sun, revolved round the Earth) was directly
deduced from Aristotle’s theories. Ptolemy, an astronomer who did most of his
works in Alexandria, Egypt, had to publish a work with the title The Almagest in
A.D. 150.
Page14
The geocentric theory was the dominant view of the universe for several
centuries. As a matter of fact, it was not until 1543 when a Polish monk named
Nicholai Copernicus proposed a heliocentric theory, according to which the Sun
was seen as the centre of the Universe, with all other planets, including the Earth,
revolving round the Sun. In his essay, “The Fall of Aristotelian and Ptolemaic
System”, Enyimba Maduka notes that one of the reasons why the Copernican
system overthrew the Aristotelian/Ptolemaic system was that “Copernicus
geometrically placed the sun at the centre of the universe and had the earth orbit
it, thus, reducing the unweidling number of epicycles from 80 to 34” (210), a
claim he attributes to Chris Butler. Of course, as at that time, the idea of a
moving Earth was absolutely mind-bogging to men without secular mentality,
especially religious bigots. Indeed, it was branded “Heresy”. And even for those
who understand the veracity of the Copernican position, it was thought at that
time that the planetary motion was circular. However, that was to change later
when the young mathematician, Johannes Kepler (1571-1630), discovered an
elliptical rather than a circular orbit.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
For the postmodern attitude in science to be proposed, propagated and
grounded, certain conceptions and perceptions of the scientific enterprise had to
be jettisoned. That science is a rational endeavor is a view vigorously and
rigorously pursued by the Austrian philosopher of science, Karl R. Popper (1902-
1994). This accounts for why he spent a large chunk of his 92 years, resources
and works trying to distinguish science, not just from non-science, but equally
from what he called “pseudo-science”. His battle with historicism, especially of
the Marxian type, is well expressed in his popular works; notably, [The Poverty
of Historicism] and the two volumes of [The Open Society and its Enemies], as
well as [Conjectures and Refutations]. Popper argues that science makes progress
by “bold conjectures and the critical search for what is false in our various
competing theories”(52) which, for him, materialist dialectical method is not
capable of doing. He, therefore, holds Marxism guilty of what he called
“reinforced dogmatism”. In [Conjectures and Refutations] for example Popper
writes that:
Hegelian dialectic, or its materialistic version, cannot be accounted as a
sound basis for scientific forecasts. Thus if forecasts based on dialectic
are made, some will come true, and some will not. In the latter case,
obviously, a situation will arise which has not been foreseen. But
dialectic is vague and elastic enough to interpret and to explain this
unforeseen situation just as it interpreted and explained the situation
which it predicted and which happened not to come truth. (333)
Our interest here is not really on Popper’s intellectual battle against Platonism,
Hegelianism or Marxism. We are citing him because he represents a classical
expression of what modern science represented: methodological exactness and
the dogged search for truth.
Page15
Consequently, the very first thing we notice about postmodernism in
science is that it had to attack the colossal image of science, it had to debunk the
view not only that rationality is the basis for modernity, but equally the view that
sees in modern science the best representation, glorification and expression of
that rationality! The issue gained currency that modern science cannot become
the ground for the justification of reality when it rests on grounds that themselves
need to be justified. In other words, how can we accept (or justify the
correctness of) the measurement taken with the ruler (or metre, or tape) of
modern science when we are asking for the justification for using the ruler, in the
first place? John Kekes, in his essay, “Recent Trends and Future Prospects in
Epistemology”, explores some of these arguments.
The next edifice that had to be pulled-down to pave way for the
postmodern conception of science was the idea of the “unity of science”, that is,
that “science is science” irrespective of what the subject-matter is. For instance,
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
at inception, and in order to be listed in the fashionable and “respectful” science
“hall-of-fame”, what became known as “social sciences” wanted to ape the
method of physical sciences hollow. Of course, at the dawn of modernity in the
17th century, when the idea of a prescribed methodology, was muted, it was
possible to even imagine it because there was only one fully developed science,
physics, or more specifically Newtonian Mechanics. Newton was so permeating
in the modern period that his six-step of scientific enquiry was for long the
dominant “method of science”. Bertrand Russell, in [History of Western
Philosophy] makes a parody of the Biblical story of the beginning of all things.
In a poetic expression Russell writes: “Nature and Nature’s laws lay hid in the
dark, God said, Let Newton be’, and all was light”(523) for Russell “almost
everything that distinguishes the modern period from earlier centuries is
attributable to science, which achieved its most spectacular triumph in the
seventeenth century (512).
The purpose of the postmodern rejection of a “unified science” is
postmodernly simple: a unified science is an attempt to create a grandstand where
all sciences would converge and that would lead to the demand for a single
standard for legitimization. The result would, obviously, be a regimentation—the
emergence of a trans-scientific, narrative for all the sciences. Yet, but what the
postmodernists want is a multiplicity of methods; that is, let each science or
scientific enquiry articulate its methods and procedures in line with its subject-
matter.
Having laid these brief foundations, I think that the stage is set for us to
discuss Kuhn and Feyerabend as exemplars of the postmodern attitude in science.
Kuhn on Scientific Revolutions
A clearer and better understanding of what we have called “postmodernism in
science” now begins with a consideration of the thoughts of Thomas S. Kuhn.
Kuhn begins his ground breaking book, [The Structure of Scientific Revolutions]
by beaming a critical searchlight on the colossal, or rather bogus, image of
science as the paradigm of institutionalized rationality. With an exploration of the
history of science and an examination of the actual practice of science, Kuhn’s
discovery and conclusion was that this towering image can be debunked.
Page16
The radical form of epistemological relativism usually associated with
and charged to Kuhn emanated from the theory of the incommensurability of
paradigms which he espoused. In the opinion of Harris, although many of the
issues that have led to the rise in the plethora of views about the image of science
have been raised earlier by people like David Hume and Charles Pierce, “these
debates are now explicitly formulated within the philosophy of science, and the
stakes certainly have been raised. On the table now are the very rationality of
science itself and the viability of epistemology as a philosophical enterprise. The
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
ugly specter of relativism is raised, Skepticism is clothed in new sheep’s
clothing, and science is in danger of becoming… just another ideology” (73).
After laying the foundation of his discussion by throwing a swipe at the
image of science via a consideration of the history of science and what scientists
themselves do, Kuhn proceeds by considering what he calls the period of normal
science. This period is the period when the members of a particular scientific
community share a common model or paradigm; that is, when every member of
that community refers to or works from a common “theory laboratory”. Many
commentators find Kuhn’s idea of paradigm very vague and too elastic. In fact,
in their edited work, [Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge], Imre Lakatos and
A. Musgrave (59-90) quotes one Masterman as identifying about 22 different
senses in which Kuhn used the term “paradigm”. We shall get back to this
challenge later when we would be carrying out a concluding critique in this
essay; but our major concern here is that understanding the idea of a “paradigm”
is crucial to understanding Kuhn’s conception of “normal science”. Early in The
Structure of Scientific Revolution, Kuhn refers to paradigms as what “provide
models from which spring particular coherent traditions of scientific research”
(10), but later in the book (174- 190), he launches into a fuller expression of the
meaning (s), content(s) of paradigms. Kuhn captures the relationship between
paradigms, the scientific community and normal science, in the following words:
The study of Paradigm … is what mainly prepares the student for
membership in the particular scientific community with which he will
later practice. Because he there joins men who learn the basis of their
field from the same concrete models, his subsequent practice will
seldom invoke overt disagreement over fundamentals. Men whose
researches are based on shared paradigms are committed to the same
rules and standards for scientific practice. That commitment and the
apparent consensus it produces are prerequisites for normal science,
i.e., for the genesis and continuation of a particular research tradition.
(10-11)
Page17
This kind of “gentleman’s agreement” and respect for a particular paradigm (it is
not a legislated action, there is some sought of voluntary compulsion to have a
feeling of not just belonging but equally belongingness to the “exalted scientific
community), and the continued reliance on that paradigm to solve problems
within the scientific community, clearly define the period of normal science. As
Newton-Smith correctly captures it, “during this period, the energies of members
of the community are given over to solving Puzzles defined by the paradigm,
which is itself based on some significant achievement” (107).
He, however, argues that because Kuhn’s use of the term “paradigm” is
“vague”, it would be hard to suppose that the periods of what Kuhn called
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
“normal science” can be clearly defined. However, as to whether there can be
periods of agreement, by a scientific community, on both theoretical assumptions
and on the problems to be solved, there can be no doubt. If anomalies are
detected during normal science, they are treated as problems to be solved rather
than as something that refutes the theory.
According to Kuhn, there would come a time when the number of
unsolved puzzles as well as the anomalies would mount. This would
automatically result in a crisis of confidence by the sharing scientific community.
The agreement that was the basis for the sharing of the paradigm would begin to
break as alternative theories are articulated. At this period, when faith is lost in an
existing paradigm, a revolution, analogous to political revolution, would occur
within the scientific community. In drawing this analogy with political
revolution, Kuhn argues that under “normal” political circumstances, there is
agreement on the means of decision making, but in revolutionary situations,
some individuals attempt to change the society by force through the creation of a
new framework for decision making. In Kuhn’s own words:
As in political revolution, so in paradigm choice—there is no standard
higher than the assent of the relevant community. To discover how
scientific revolutions are affected, we shall, therefore, have to examine,
not only the impact of nature and logic, but also the techniques of
argumentative persuasion effective within the quite special groups that
constitute the community of scientists. (94)
The implication of the above is that historical and sociological factors are
indispensable in science. Propaganda becomes a crucial factor in science. As
Kuhn again says; “the normal scientific tradition that emerges from scientific
revolution is not only incompatible but often actually incommensurable with that
which has gone before (102).
The focus on paradigm is about the most important contribution made to
the philosophy of science by Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions. From a
somewhat “preparadigmatic” era, Kuhn characterizes a period of agreement
among the scientific community on the model for methods, techniques and
questions in science. According to Harris, ‘the single most-important and, at the
same time, one of the most controversial aspects of Kuhn’s science is that it is
paradigm based” (76).
Page18
That an aspiring scientist must be aware of the paradigm of a scientific
community, that only there from can he consciously proceed if he wants to be a
fruitful and accepted member of that community, and that the loss of faith in a
particular shared model (paradigm) results in a situation similar to that of the
Biblical “to your tents Oh Israel”, appear to be Kuhn’s innovative position. It is
in the emergence of a new paradigm after the revolution (let us call it Normal
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
Science-Next, NS-N) that our postmodern interest in Kuhn lies. According to
Kuhn:
If two men disagree, for example, about the relative fruitfulness of
their theories, or if they agree about that but disagree about the relative
importance of fruitfulness and say, scope in reaching a choice neither
can be convicted of a mistake, nor is either being unscientific. There is
no neural algorithm for theory- choice, no systematic decision
procedure which, properly applied, must lead each individual in the
group to the same decision. (199-200)
The Kuhnian position has been perceived as post-modernist or post-positivist
because of the way he characterized the nature of the occurrence of the
revolutionary shift from the old to the new paradigm. Kuhn has characterized that
change as a “sudden and unstructured event” and it would appear that reasoning
oneself into a new paradigm is impossible since Kuhn says that the guiding
motivation for accepting the new paradigm “can only be made on faith”. Science
becomes another ideology like religion. For him, “proponents of competing
paradigms are always at least slightly at cross-purposes” (148). James Harris
clearly explains Kuhn’s position in the following words:
The new paradigm which replaces the old one during a scientific
revolution is, according to Kuhn, “incommensurable” with the old
paradigm, that is: since the new paradigm “necessitates a redefinition”
of the old and since the standards and criteria for the evaluation of
paradigms are internal to the paradigms, it follows that the change from
the old paradigm to the new one cannot come about by appealing to
some neutral criteria or method of paradigm selection. Perhaps most
importantly, the replacement process is not the old, familiar
falsification/ verification process from science before the revolution
where certain data might either falsify or verify one paradigm or the
other. Since the new paradigm is incommensurable with the old, the
process of abandoning the old in favor of the new cannot be a gradual,
logical or “scientific” process based upon evidence or some form of
reasoning. (78)
Page19
Let us try to itemize Kuhn’s position from what Harris has just said: the
emergence of a new paradigm for NS-N is seen as postmodernist because: one,
the new paradigm was not a logical or systematic (or even dialectical) deduction
from the old paradigm. This means that the question of building from the past
upon which science thrives does not arise; Two, the new paradigm was not
selected from a kind of neutral pool of paradigms whose legitimacy is vouched
for by the members of the scientific community. In other words, there is no
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
“respectable” or “respected” paradigm or class of paradigms that the scientific
community accepts (or had accepted), and which the community invests with the
toga of finality or authority when it comes to paradigm choice, no paradigm
adjudicator with a mandate such as: “if there is a disagreement on paradigms
choice or if there is loss of confidence in or failure of an existing paradigm,
provide a new one”. A third reason for the postmodernist characterizing of Kuhn
is because the new paradigm that emerges from the revolutionary period is not
based on the old principles of falsification (a la Popper) or verification (a la
Logical Positivism).
However, a major question needs to be asked at this point, especially as
it relates to the third reason given above: why must the failure of the new
paradigm to have its base on Popper’s Falsification and the Verification principle
of logical positivism become an issue? Are the Logical positivists and Popper the
only propounders of scientific methodologies? Well, to address the matter
straight away, we need to remember Popper’s frontal important role in perceiving
science as a rational enterprise. He was a leading figure in the conception of the
place of science in the overall development of the twentieth century. When it
comes to Logical Positivism, the place of the movement in the growth of science
is more of a reference point in almost all discussions on and about science. In his
small but insight-lending book: [The Philosophy of Logical Positivism and the
Growth of Science], G. O. Ozumba reminds us that the movement marks “a
turning point in the history and development of ideas” (9), and notes the fact that
the movement concentrated on the “observable” and the rejection of metaphysics.
But if Ozumba did a critique of logical positivism, Harris was more critical of the
project of the logical positivists. In fact, according to Harris, it was the failure of
the project of logical positivism that opened up the modern period to a barrage of
punches (of criticism) and then inaugurated the postmodern relativistic
alternative. For Harris, the disappointment of a few men promising a lot to many
(with their Verification Principle) and failing to deliver, just led to the belief that
the last stronghold of modernity has collapsed (7). The issue here is not really on
logical positivism. We rather want to provide explanation for why the failure of
Kuhn’s analysis to conform to the Verification Principle should become
important. The objectivity usually claimed for the Verification Principle is denied
in Kuhn since the criteria for judging or evaluating each paradigm is internal not
external to it.
Page20
However, before we proceed to look at Feyerabend, it is important to briefly
look at the so-called “shift of position” by Kuhn. We need must note that every
(philosophical) position taken by a scholar is read, studied, analyzed and
interpreted. The thesis of the “incommensurability of paradigms” put forward by
Kuhn was interpreted to mean that he has voted for “irrationality” and of courses,
radical relativism, with the legendary difficulties associated with them. In his
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
essay, “Reflections on My Critics”, Kuhn attempts further explanation and
clarification of his position when he writes that:
My critics respond to my view on this subject (the incommensurability
of paradigms) with charges of irrationality, relativism and the defense
of mob rule. These are all labels which I categorically reject even when
they are used in my defense… To say that, in matters of theory choice,
the force of logic and observation cannot in principle be compelling is
neither to defend logic and observation nor to suggest that there are not
good reasons for favouring one theory over another. (234)
Relativism of the radical incommunicating type as well as irrationality
juxtaposed with the Western conception of rationality (as logical consistency), is
so emptily and negatively construed that no Western scholar would want to
proudly and brazenly be associated with them, because they do not see the
complementarity between the rational and the irrational, the relative and the
objective. So, no one needs to blame Kuhn for wanting to wash his hands off
such associations, either positively or negatively.
Kuhn, in this shift of position is interpreted as suggesting simply that
there is no “neutral algorithm for theory choice” (200) and not that one cannot
proffer “good reason” to justify the preference of one theory over another.
Understood in this latter sense, Kuhn, it is assumed, would not be seen as a brash
irrationalist. In the opinion of Harris, Kuhn, in the explanation for the so-called
shift, wants to retain the notion of incommensurability but in a “moderate” (89)
and “weakened” (90) way. We must pause now on Kuhn (we would return to it
when we carry out a critical conclusion of this essay) to consider another
iconoclastic analyst of the image of science, Paul Feyerabend.
Feyerabend and the two Pillars of Modern Science
Page21
Maybe it was intentional, maybe it was not; but when Paul Feyerabend wrote his
two most popular books, [Against Method] (1975) and [Farewell to Reason]
(1987), he struck two bomb-like blows at the two Pillars of modernity: Science
and Reason. When Feyerabend’s book, [Against Method] appeared, it sought to
provide equal access to questions of method and perception of result for other
traditions such as astrology, Witchcraft and traditional medicine. Newton-Smith
called [Against Method] the most “lively or entertaining critique of the scientific
method” (125). For him the work could have been titled [Against Received
Opinion]. For Feyerabend, there is nothing sacrosanct or special about science
because there is no clear difference, in method and result, between science and
other traditions.
Although Feyerabend usually rejects the influence of Karl Popper on
him, it is not difficult to observe that influence. After all, both of them, at one
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
time, taught at the London School of Economics and Political Science. What
Feyerabend opposes when he speaks of “method in science is the idea of
selecting, adopting or relying on a system of rules that would generate a logic of
justification or guiding compass that would help scientists to legitimately make
theory choices. Science thrives and makes progress by claiming that there is
such a universal notion of human understanding and that if humankind is able to
grasp it, then progress can be made at all fronts In [Farewell to
Reason].”Feyerabend pejoratively describes such claims as “conceited, ignorant,
superficial, incomplete and dishonest” (25). In a yet to be published essay, “On
the Diction of Postmodernists” I have not only discussed and analyzed a plethora
of such adjectives, I have equally suggested reasons why postmodernists use such
derogatory, debasing, confrontational and polemic terms when discussing
modernity and its harbingers.
Newton-Smith appears to summarize Feyerabend’s project in [Against
Method] when he says that he (Feyerabend) “stands against the venerable
tradition of searching for a system of rules which it is held ought to guide
scientists in the business of theory choice” (126).
Feyerabend does not accept the doctrine or principle of Cummulativism,
according to which scientific knowledge is acquired piecemeal through
observation, formulation of theories and experimentation. Cummulativism, as
Princewill Alozie explains, in [History and Philosophy of Science]:
If T1 is an accepted scientific theory for a given period and there
emerged a new theory T2 which could explain things that T1 could not
explain; as long as T1 was empirically confirmed initially, then T2 will
necessarily include T1. But T1 and T2 are about a given phenomenon.
If there is a third theory, T3 which has more explanatory power than
the first two, then we shall be having series is knowledge that are
linked up thus: T1–T2-T3-. (155)
In rejecting the cumulative model, Feyerabend argued that the words used in
formulating the different theories would have had changes in their meanings and
so the theories cannot be linked with themselves in the attempt to address a
particular phenomenon. This rejection of piecemeal acquisition of theories is
similar to Kuhn’s view that a new paradigm is incommensurable with an old one.
We must remember that Feyerabend’s attack on science is on the concept
Page22
of method. Of course, there are two activities which methodological concerns in
science usually cover: First, what rules are there for the discovery of theories and
what principles can we objectively use to justify our evaluation of rival theories.
In other words, if we want to discover theories in science, are there laid-down
rules to be followed in doing so? Second, when it comes to preferring one theory
over another or evaluating the explanatory content of two or more theories are
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
there principles (as fundamental truths) that we can possibly rely on to justify our
choice? These are the two broad issues that are traditionally held to be the focus
of methodological concerns in modern science.
Not only does Feyerabend reject a distinction between these two activities of
discovery and justification; he proceeded to reject that science has a method. For
him, in [Against Method]:
The idea of method that contains firm, unchanging and absolutely
binding principles for conducting the business of science meets
considerable difficulty when confirmed with the results of historical
research. We find then, that there is not a single rule, however plausible,
and however grounded in epistemology, that is not violated at some time
or other. (23)
Feyerabend rejects the view that science is a rational activity; he debunks the
claim that science, in method and result, can be clearly distinguished from myth,
religion, philosophy, astrology and even ideology. The charge of
“epistemological anarchism” is usually leveled against Feyerabend. This is
sequel to his claim that:
It is clear then, that the idea of a fixed method or of a fixed theory of
rationality, rests on too naive a view of man and his social
surroundings… it becomes clear that there is only one principle that can
be defended under all circumstances and in every stage of human
development. It is the principle anything goes! (27-28)
The charge of “mob-psychology”, “cognitive egalitarianism”, “anything-goes
relativism” etc., have been variously leveled at Feyerabend and his postmodern
colleagues in the philosophy of science. But no matter the charge, Feyerabend’s
focus should not be forgotten: that there is nothing special about science. As he
says again that logic and arguments cannot make science any better than it is. In
another monumental later book, [Farewell to Reason], Feyerabend says that “the
idea of a science that proceeds by logically rigorous argumentations is nothing
but a dream (43)”.
Page23
What Feyerabend means by “anything goes” is not that there are no
methods which sciences in various forms or which scientists use. What he is
against is the thought of making or perceiving science as rationality per
excellence, which contains one method. Again, he says that his argument does
not directly encourage the proliferations of methods or theories. He later argued
that all he had done was to show that the rationalist cannot possibly exclude
proliferation of methods. He suggests that the Galilean example should be
imitated: he did not succumb to the paradigm or method of his day. That way,
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
progress was ensured. No wonder Newton-Smith refers to Feyerabend as “a
paradigm case of … a non rationalist” (126).
What Feyerabend appears to be arguing for can be expressed thus:
“Hey”, dear rationalists, would you by adopting your rationalist method/theory
also (at the same time and automatically) exclude someone else from holding on
to and adopting a method/theory that does not conform to your criterion (or
criteria) of rationality? In other words, the rationalist cannot simply by adopting a
position assume that the mere fact that he took that position would prevent, stop,
prohibit or disallow the possibility of holding on to a counter rational position.
In [Science in a Free Society], Feyerabend disagrees that proving that a
system is inconsistent, as the rationalists do many times is even a proof that there
is something wrong with the system since even inconsistent theories, have
brought about progress in science (210-211). He further posits that this desire and
demand for rules of logical consistency without exceptions would end up
becoming indefinite and, consequently embracing of everything (128).
At the end of the day, Feyerabend was overall interested in showing that
science is just one ideology among many others. He chose to critically strike at
the two fundamental pillars of modern science: Method and Reason
(Rationality)!
Although, science has laid claim to several technological breakthrough,
the consensus of opinion appears to be that science (and its method) is only but
one cognitive approach to the vast array of reality. As Alozie concludes for us:
The history and method of science give it the colour of any other
ideology or world-view. Some of the claims of science are similar in
character or “truth-content”, to myths and religion. There is the
excellence and superiority of science and also the imperialist powers
who do not allow other cultures to make their contribution to the body
of knowledge that can improve the world. Might appear to be right. In
quite a large measure, Paul Feyerabend is correct in his criticism of
how science is perceived… it has been discovered that the word
“science” may not have a great technological value. Science has to be
co-joined with technology for political and economic reasons. The
under-developed and impoverished majority of world population need
to learn that there is an ideology which is superior to their various
religions, myths and cultural values. That superior ideology is science.
(160)
Page24
Of course, science is philosophy, especially when we realize that “Scientia”
means “to know”, which is the same thing as “episteme”, from where the term
“epistemology”, a major branch of Philosophy, is derived. Science, as Alozie has
just noted had to become “science and technology” in order to become a practical
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
discipline. As “science”, building theories and discovering laws are the central
concerns, but as “technology”, it would involve lighting bursen-burners and
mixing chemicals.
Conclusion: Implications for Africa
Fortunately, the only thing being concluded here is the text of this essay, the
issues at stake here are not being concluded (and may never be). There are so
many things involved in addressing the thoughts of Kuhn and Feyerabend, on the
one hand, and the debate between postmodernists and modern science/rationality,
on the other. We have only used Kuhn and Feyerabend as examples of the
postmodern attitude to science. Attempting to grapple with the complexities of
the issues would be unnecessary, even impossible, here.
While Kuhn considered the history and actual practice of science as the
basis for rejecting the bogus image of science, Feyerabend argued that in terms of
method and result, modern science is just one way of cognizing reality, among
many others. No doubt, like all other issues that domiciles within the
philosophical discourse, they have many supporters and critics, but we won’t go
into much details to consider the (de)merits of each. A fundamental question
needs to be asked at this point: what really was the problem with modern science
that makes postmodernism get so much attention, even when one disagrees with
it? In other words, is the postmodern attitude in science (and postmodernism in
general) just some gibberish, some play with words?
This way of interpreting or understanding the word “science” is too
exclusive, too restrictive for participation by other cultures. But what is “science”
but an articulation of an understanding of the Laws of nature? And are we
concluding that only the Western world had the capacity to understand nature? It
is also the case that when tools or equipments are fashioned or adapted, in line
with this understanding, in order to confront the environment and improve
humankind’s existence, it is called “technology”. Neither science, nor its
practical output, technology, is an exclusive preserved of any culture. Having set
the pace, as a result of colonial conquest, the West has made those of us in Africa
to get into a desperate rat race to “prove” that we “have” philosophy, science,
religion, history, etc in line (unfortunately) with the conceptual schemes of the
West.
Page25
Newton-Smith has argued that “Feyerabend… is much more radical in
his critique of rationalism than Kuhn. Kuhn holds that there are rules held in
common by all members of the scientific community” (126). But from history,
practice and results of science, we have agreed to a large extent, that the
theorization, systemization and Kant-ization of knowledge in the modern period
led to a visceral regimentation of reality. Modern science appeared not only to
have appropriated knowledge, but actually “arrested” and “detained” it in the
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
intellectual and scholarly “Concentration Camp” of Western bookish,
scholarship, nay school-ship form. Anyone that wants to have access to
knowledge must have to pass through the guarding-Gestapo of an imposing
Epistemology, the allusion to Kant here is crucial because he is the source of the
foundationalism that postmodernists reject. In my essay “A Critique of the
Critical Philosophy of Immanuel Kant”, I have discussed some of these issues,
especially with regard to Rorty’s claim that it was Kant that made epistemology
“self conscious”
Lyotard has argued that knowledge is broader than science, since scientific
knowledge is “narrative” which means that it appeals to a single, grand scheme
(78). For him, science rejects other narratives, branding them “fables, myths and
legends”. But the postmodern condition contains measures that build competence
and they are derived from culture and custom. Legitimization, therefore, must be
based on socio-political and on ethnocentric grounds. The result is that
epistemology becomes sociology. For Lyotard, therefore, “all we can do is gaze
in wonderment at the diversity of discursive species, just as we do at the diversity
of plant and animal species (80).
Of course, when we use “science” here, we mean specifically “modern
Western science”, because “science” is not a Western word. It is a way of
understanding or explaining reality, and it exists in all cultures. Without getting
into the semantic battle of what it is for any concept to be “African” (see for
instance, S.B. Oluwole’s) “the Africanness of a Philosophy”, J.I Unah’s “Can a
Work Be Both African and Philosophy”, and J.O. Oguejiofor’s “How African is
Communalism”), I want to suggest that Jonathan O. Chimakonam’s new,
courageous and insight- lending book, [Introducing African Science…] is a work
given birth to by the spirit of multiplicity and plurality championed by the
postmodern attitude. What Chimakonam refers to as “letting other cocks crow
besides one”, a condition which is perceived as a transgression of “the
boundaries of reason and the custom of the salient community” (3), is an allusion
to and opening of what Rorty had earlier called “cultural space”.
Page26
In my paper “Africa Within the Globe: Confronting the Parameters of
Cross-Cultural Philosophy”, I had argued that those of us in the African
continent, and others in the Diaspora committed to Africa’s course, appeared to
have shot ourselves in the foot when we began to talk of “African Philosophy”
instead of “philosophy in Africa”. For philosophy is a universal endeavor and
activity which exists and is carried out anywhere Homo sapiens dwell. The
debate as to what makes anything “African” appears to be unresolved, since
geography, birth and color may not be very helpful. The issue at stake here is not
these debates. The point of interest here is the fact that postmodern hermeneutics
created the pedestal for the thoughts of different cultures to be displayed, not to
be judged against the backdrop of Western cannon of rationality, but to be
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
appreciated and described within the context of its own natural habitat. In my
essay, “The Spectacles of Inter-cultural Philosophy: Same Frame, Different
Lenses”, I have discussed the possibility; goals, need and challenges of an
intercultural philosophy. At least, the possibility of an intercultural philosophy is
a pointer that we do not have to, as it were, be conquered by the radical, non
communicating relativism that postmodernists often brandish.
Although many have regarded as gross distortions” the interpretation that
Kuhn’s positions are skeptical and relativistic, it is obvious that his claim of
emergence of competing paradigms at the dawn of “revolutionary Science”,
aligns him with the plurality that is the hallmark of the post-modern era. No
wonder Robert Baun and Feyerabend, in “Popper, Kuhn, Lakatos: A Crisis of
Modern Intellect” regards as “intellectual anarchism” any position that could be
interpreted as being the end of the reign of Reason (181).
Now, does Kuhn’s claim that the criterion for problem solving is
INTERNAL to a particular paradigm also mean that the criterion for selecting or
choosing one paradigm over another is also internal? One of the mercurial
philosophers of science of our era, Israel Schefler, in his book, Science and
Subjectivity, said, and rightly too, that the kind of puzzles and their solutions
may, and in fact does differ, from paradigm but it does not mean that one cannot
reasonably argue over paradigms (202). Kuhn’s famous “irrationality thesis”,
therefore,
cannot be defended. The limitations imposed by the
incommensurability of paradigm are enough for the acceptance of the impossible
rational theory choice. For Kuhn, that limitation makes it both difficult and
impossible “for an individual to hold both theories in mind together and compare
them point by point with each other and with nature. That sort of comparison is,
however, the process on which the appropriateness of any word like “choice”
depends (Kuhn, The Structure…, 168).
Kuhn had hinged his decision on the incommensurability of paradigms on the
view that the concepts used in formulating the paradigm have different meanings
and applications. Kuhn’s popular example of what he means is shown in his
claim that when Copernicus’ heliocentric view of the solar system was accepted
in place of Ptolemy’s view, it was made possible via the denial of the title of
“Planet” to the Sun, while it was not denied to the Earth. (Kuhn, The Structure….
128). That way, there was a change in the very meaning of the concept “planet”.
Page27
Those who accuse the postmodernists of playing with words or relying
heavily on analysis of worlds forget that we communicate our thoughts with
words or language. When it is argued that the postmodernists reject the very idea
of “truth” (Kuhn, for e.g., SSR, 170), it is truth absolutized, regimented and
canonized. However, in the essay “Reply to Criticism”, Feyerabend clearly
argued that the notion of incommensurability is actually independent of the
theory of Invariance in meaning (231-234). Andrew Sayer, in his
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
“Postmodernism and the Three ‘pomo’ Flips” says that in the final analysis,
postmodernists end up “refusing all talk of truth and falsity, denying any kind of
relationship between thought and world” (69)
This type of attack on and defense of relativism (especially) is popular
and available within scholarly circles, so much so that they are beginning to
sound like cracked records. For example, against the type of criticisms pursued
by people like Sayer, Jonathan Chua Yi in his paper “A Postmodern Defense of
Thomas Kuhn” argues that:
Despite showing all signs of belonging to the postmodern camp, Kuhn
can be defended by arguing that relativism is necessitated by the way
human understanding is itself structured. Although critics like Andrew
Sayer might want to argue that reliable knowledge is still possible, it
remains an unfortunate “truth” that even the standards of scientific
objectivity are socially determined by the prevailing paradigm of
science. What is important is not to ignore postmodernism or take a
defeatist attitude toward it, but to approach it positively, for by
disclosing the sociology underlying knowledge itself, we are made
more aware not to take things at face value, not even truth itself. (Web
N. P)
Page28
It does appear, in the long run, that those who feel the jitters when relativism
comes to the fore, forget that the world needs the individuality and particularity
offered by a relativistic attitude to build bulwark against the mental castration
created by a standardization that is itself a product of a few. What Kuhn and
Feyerabend appear to be saying, and which I agree with, is that one requires more
than theories and method to be part of a community of scientists. The rules and
principles that guide one’s choice of the theory or method, and which set the
standards for justification of the choice, are not intrinsic to the theory or method.
They must be sought outside them; they must be society-determined. Besides,
Harris has voted for the relativism of the Goodman-type. According to him
“Goodman’s version of relativism is a relativity mild-mannered, one with little or
no serious consequences for the traditional scientific and epistemological notions
of rationality” (72). Again, this is stark-raving Western intellectual bigotry. Does
the mere fact of a lack of “serious consequences” for traditional Western notion
of rationality, secure the acceptance of a particular brand of relativism? Who is
making the rules here? Once again, Harris’s defense of Rationality Westerna
throws it face down with a broken nose! That’s exactly the point that
postmodernists are making: you don’t set the standards from your own pedestal,
with your own conceptual schemes, and then illegitimately legislate it as standard
for all cultures.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
If there is anything the postmodern attitude in science has done, it is to
apply speed-breakers on the racing track of modern science, a break that ensures
that modern science does not race into its own destruction. Somehow,
postmodernism’s speed breakers on the tracks of modern science have provided
liberation for the models of knowing and given them a voice to be liberated from
this modern authoritarianism.
This is why in, [African Philosophy Through Ubuntu], Mogobe B.
Ramose insists that the way the colonized people conceive reality, knowledge
and truth has been in the penitentiary of “European epistemological paradigm”
and would need to be released in order to engender what he calls “a common,
authentic and liberating universe of discourse”. And to be candid, I agree with his
insistence that “African philosophy contains an in eliminable liberative
dimension”. For him, “the imperative for the authentic liberation of Africa
requires neither a supplicative apologia nor an interminable obsecious defense of
being an Africa” (4). Part of the reason why I appreciate Ramose’s work is the
“liberating dimension” it pursues. For indeed Africans need mental liberation
before Africa would be socio-economically liberated.
The postmodern hermeneutic cleaning of the cultural space of all the
occupying tendencies of Western epistemological theories should be an entry
point for Africa to demand to be heard- and in her own terms. This is why I
suggested that African philosophers should quit “Reflection” and develop a
“Refl-active” mentality. In my essay “The Principle of Refl-action” as the Basis
for a Culture of philosophy in African”, I had suggested that the need to create a
culture of “philosophizing” in Africa can best be served by a principle that
ensures that the African “thinks –to- do” (refl-acts) instead of the luxury of the
armchair philosophy introduced by colonial education.
Modern science, with its concomitant rationality and method, should be
conceived and perceived as just another mode of cognition. In her daring book,
[The Earth Unchained. A Quantum Leap in Consciousness], Catherine Acholonu
has noted that “Qantum Physics is a science that has proved classical scientists
wrong and the philosopher right. Quantum mechanics is the science of the
humanist, the psychologist, the philosopher, the mystic…” (69). At the level of
“quanti”, exactness disappears in science. After all, at the time when modern
science was talking about a prescriptive methodology that would suffice all the
sciences, there was only one fully developed science- physics, or more
specifically, Newtonian Mechanics. But now, the discussion of methodology has
superseded the Newtonian type.
Page29
In an earlier paper, “The Mode of Knowledge in Science and Social
Science”, I observed that under the influence of Ernst Mach, Karl Pearson etc.. A
new idea emerged to the effect that science is merely an accurate description of
the world. For Mach, it did not matter what method the scientists followed in
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
describing as economically and as accurately as possible so as to be able to make
predictions; what really mattered was that his predictions came out with a high
probability. Also recent development in Cybernetics has shown that the
traditional structure and method of science could not suffice the needs of
contemporary science. Mach’s Sensationalism, with its emphasis on sense data,
has stimulated a new interest in the nature of the empirical evidence on which
science is based. Albert Einstein’s Theory of Relativity and developed quantum
mechanics precipitated a new crisis in Physics. This crisis later generated the
methodological doctrine of P. W. Bridgeman. Bridgeman formulated the theory
known as Operationism or Operationalism, according to which the concepts
employed in scientific theories, must be defined in terms of actual Operations
carried out by the scientists in measuring their quantitative values. Rudolf
Carnap advocated an inductive logic according to which the important thing
about scientific propositions is that they are confirmable in terms of available
evidence, while Karl Popper believes that science does not use the inductive
method but rather uses the hypothetico-deductive method.
Contemporary discussions of methodology have a tendency to pass into
metaphysical or epistemological considerations. Such discussions do not really
affect theory choice by working scientists. The philosophical content of
methodological enquiries has changed also. Instead of the search for a unique
scientific method, the general conclusion seems to be that the method of science
is an admixture of logical construction and empirical observation.
The capacity to be logical and empirical are not exclusive preserves of
any one culture or people. Globalizing Western science marked the season of
bondage for other narratives. Cahoone’s characterization of the many
conceptions or connotations of the goal of postmodernism becomes necessary
when postmodernism is taken as a global topic. However, seen in its true
postmodern pluralistic fashion, there is nothing preventing the Western
intellectual from continuing to hang on to the “tattered flag of modernity”- as
long as from the point of view of Africa, postmodernism is perceived in its
liberating dimension. Indeed, it is both conceptually and practically impossible
for a thorough- going modernist to embrace postmodernism.
Page30
In life, nothing is also absolute; sometimes we win some, sometimes,
we lose some. Perhaps, relativism is the prize we must pay to appreciate the
plurality of cultural space provided by the postmodernists. And indeed, what is
really wrong with relativism? Why do we not complain about the fact that no two
human beings have the same deoxyribonucleic acid (DNA)? Why do we attack
relativism so much in epistemology when it exists in bio-ontology? The popular
criticism of postmodernism which says that its rejection of a grand norm, if
accepted as true, will also become a grand norm is an attempt to trivialize the
substantial issues about modernity which postmodernity addresses. Besides,
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
postmodernism, as the next-after of modernity is a useful continuation of the
attempt to develop modern concerns.
Although, I share some of the views of Edwin Etieyibo about the release
of philosophical discourses in Africa from the totalitarian and universalizing
hegemony of the Enlightenment project, I have certain areas that I feel
uncomfortable about his analysis. One, the fact that we are still struggling to
explain the content and nature of the concept “African philosophy” appears to be
a self-imposed challenge. If one goes through Sophie B. Oluwole’s “The
Africanness of a Philosophy” (1989) and Jim. I. Unah’s “Can a Work Be Both
African and Philosophy?” (2002) Problem of the Locution “African philosophy”
unveils itself to us. For indeed, what makes a work in philosophy “African”
becomes altogether difficult to decipher with any degree of exactness. On several
occasions, I have argued that philosophy is a specific human activity and exists
anywhere humans are. It is not a Western, African, Asian or Biafran activity, but
it is found in the West, Africa, Asia, Biafra or wherever.
What we have called “African philosophy” or (imagine) “African Ethics”
are nothing but philosophical or ethnical reflections in and for Africa. When
systematic academic philosophy began in the West, it was not called “Western
Philosophy”. It was simply called “philosophy”!
Second, Etieyibo’s identification of human-centeredness, prescriptivity
and normativity as features of what he calls “African Ethics” and which make it
“susceptible to the same sort of worries that post-modernity raises for modern
thinking” (79) gives the impression that these features are exclusive to ethical
discourses in Africa. But it is not so, before the advent of linguisticism in
philosophy, Ethics was (and still remains largely) a normative discourse.
Metaethics came later when philosophers, in their self- styled desire to remain
relevant and “keep-communicating”, decided to begin word-analysis. Although
this may be necessary, but how significant does my coming to know the diverse
meaning of the term “good” contribute to my being a good man? A careful
reading of Etieyibo’s essay, seems to place before those who reflect on Africa’s
realities a choice to make: either they accept postmodernism’s pluralistic opening
of the “cultural space” which provided them the platform to (at least) be heard in
their own terms or remain in the foundational objective state imposed by their
orientation and pedagogic introduction to Western philosophical thinking.
Page31
We cannot end this essay without a word on what is known as
Transmodernity, a term coined in 1989 by the Spanish philosopher (and feminist)
Rosa Maria Rodriquez Magda. Transmodernity is a dialectical passage from
modernity to postmodernity and then the transmodern Transmodernity is more of
an attempt to salvage the best of modernity. It is the return and survival of the
part of modernity that seems submerged by the invading radical relativism of
postmodernism. Similarly, transmodernity is also post-modernity, but it is post
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
modernity without the tendency to rupture reality, albeit innocently. According to
Enrique Dussel, in his essay “Transmodernity and Interculturality: An
interpretation from the perspective of the philosophy of liberation”,
“Transmodernity points toward all of those aspects that are situated ‘beyond’
(and also ‘prior to’) the structure valorized by modern European/ North
American Culture, and which are present in other non- European universal
cultures, and have begun to move towards a pluriversal utopia” (19). The
implication of the above is that, as a utopia, pluriversality keeps us always on the
expectation for the best without losing hope.
Transmodernity believes that modernity is not even an exclusive West
European phenomenon and argues that although colonialism may have ended,
coloniality and its basic logic has remained. Transmodernity has a focus on the
liberation of cultures that has long been under the epistemological hold of
coloniality. What this means is that transmodernity is a dialectical synthesis of
the opposition between modernity and postmodernity.
Philip Idachaba and Sylvester Ogba, in their essay “Decolonizing
African
Philosophy:
Perspectives
from
Afro-Constructivism
and
Transmodernity” discuss the transmodern triune dialectical movement from
“particulars to universals and then to Pluri-versals” (42-60). What makes their
essay significant is that they discuss it against the backdrop of African
Philosophy; that is they analyze the part that Transmodernity can play in the
decolonization project/process within African philosophy.
For transmodernity, pluri-versality is a universal project. What this
means, if we interpret it properly, is that instead of the “uni-versality” of
modernity, or the ordinary plurality of postmodernity, there is a new tilt towards
“pluri-versality”. I am not, at this point, really concerned with a deep plunge into
transmodernity. It will be the focus of further research, especially on its
relationship to philosophical concerns in Africa. The implications of our
discourse for Africa can range from the acquisition of a cultural space on the
wings of postmodern thinking to the expression of ideas from a wide range of
African thought—science, philosophy, art, etc., which were hitherto silenced by
the roar of one universal reason. I simply would want to also point out that the
dispute between modernists and postmodernists is no longer germane, it is now
stale.
Modern science is no longer, ultimate wisdom.
Postmodern plurality appears to have been overtaken.
Page32
Transmordern pluri-versality is on the stage now and Africa surely has a
lot of space on that stage!
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
Relevant Literature
1.ACHOLONU, Catherine. O. [The Earth Unchained: A Quantum Leap
in Consciousness], 1995. AFA Publications: Owerri. Paperback.
2.AGBO, Joseph N. “A Critique of the Critical Philosophy of Immanuel
Kant”, [Flash: Journal of Philosophy and Religion], pp76-82, 2008. Vol
2. No 1. Paperback.
3.— . “Africa within the Globe: Confronting the Parameters of Cross
Cultural Philosophy”, [Journal of Cultural Studies], pp182-213, 2003.
Vol 5. No 2. Paperback.
4.— .“Science and the ‘End’ of Epistemology: The Implications of the
Postmodern Philosophical Hermeneutics for Africa”, [paper presented at
the Bi-annual Conference of the Nigerian Philosophical Association
(NPA), Benue State University, Makurdi], 12-15 May, 2010. U.P.
5.— .“On the Diction of Post-Modernists”. U.P.
6.— .“the principle of ‘Refl-action’ as the Basic for a Culture of
Philosophy in Africa”, [Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African
Philosophy, Culture and Religions], pp423-460, July-December, 2013.
Vol 2. No 2. Paperback.
7.— . “The Mode of Knowledge in Science and Social Science”,
[Philosophy and Logic, EZE Nwokereke Ed.], 2003. Jones Publications:
Enugu. Paperback.
8.— .“The Spectacles of Inter- Cultural Philosophy: Same frame,
Different Lenses”, [New Era Research Journal of Human, Educational
and Sustainable Development], pp43-54, 2011. Vol 5. No 1. Paperback.
9.ALOZIE, Princewill I Ed. [History and Philosophy of Science, 2nd edn.],
2001. Clear Lines Publications: Calabar. Paperback.
Page33
10. BAUN, Robert F. and FEYEREBEND, Paul. “Popper, Kuhn, Lakatos:
A Crisis of Modern Intellect”, [Science and Culture in the Western
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
Tradition: Sources and Interpretations], 1987. Gorsuch Scarishrick:
Arizona. Paperback.
11. BERTENS, Hans. [The Idea of A Postmodern: A History], 1995.
Routledge and Kegan Paul: London. Paperback.
12. BLACKBURN, Simon Ed. [Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy], 1996.
Oxford University Press: Oxford. Paperback.
13. CAHOONE, Lawrence E. [From Modernism to Postmodernism: An
Anthology], 1996. Blackwell Publishers Ltd: Oxford. Paperback.
14. CHIMAKONAM, Jonathan O. [Introducing African Science:
Systematic and Philosophical Approach], 2012.
Author House:
Bloomington. Paperback.
15. CHUA YI, Jonathan. “A postmodern Defense of Thomas Kuhn”. N. P.
Retrieved 23rd August, 2014. Web.
16. DUSSEL, Enrique “Transmodernity and Intercultuality: An
interpretation from the Philosophy of Liberation”. N. P. Retrieved 24th
August, 2014. Web.
17. ENYIMBA, Maduka. [The Fall of the Aristotelian and Ptolemaic
System, Philosophy and the Rise of Modern Science, UDUIGWOMEN,
Andrew F. Ed.], 2011. El- Johns Publishers: Uyo. Paperback.
18. ETIEYIBO, Edwin. “Postmodern Thinking and African Philosophy”,
[Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and
Religions], pp67-82, Jan-Jun, 2014. Vol 3. No 1. Paperback.
19. FEYERABEND, Paul K. [Against Method], 1975. Verso Press: New
York. Paperback.
Page34
20. — . [Farewell to Reason], 1987. Verso Press: New York. Paperback.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
21. — . “Reply to Criticism”, [Boston studies in the Philosophy of
Science, COHEN, R.S. and WARTOFSKY, M.W. Eds.], 1965.
Humanities Press: New York. Paperback.
22. — . [Science in a free Society], 1978. New Left Books: London.
Paperback.
23. GEURAS, Dean. “Richard Rorty and the Postmodern Rejection of
Absolute Truth”. N. P. Retrieved July 23, 2014. Web.
24. HARRIS, James F. [Against Relativism: A Philosophical Defense of
Method], 1993. Open Court: Illinois. Paperback.
25. IDACHABA, Philip and OGBA, Sylvester. “Decolonizing African
Philosophy:
Perspectives
from
Afro-Constructivism
and
Transmodernity”, [Frontiers of Knowledge in Philosophy: Cutting Edge
Issues, ASIEGBU, Martins and CHUKWUOKOLO, Chidozie Eds.],
pp42-60, 2014. Jones Publications: Enugu. Paperback.
26. KEKES, John. “Recent Trends and Future Prospects in
Epistemology”, [Meta-Philosophy], April to July, 1997. Vol 8. No 2. and
3. Paperback.
27. KUHN, Thomas S. [The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd edn.],
1970. The University of Chicago Press: Chicago. Paperback.
28. — . “Reflections on My Critics”, [Criticism and the Growth of
Knowledge, LAKATOS Imre and MUSGRAVE, Alan Eds.], 1970.
Cambridge University Press: Cambridge. Paperback.
29. KYMLICKA, Will. [Multicultural Citizenship], 1995. Clarendon
Press: Oxford. Paperback.
Page35
30. LAKATOS, Imre and MUSGRAVE, Alan, Eds. [Criticism and the
Growth of Knowledge], 1968. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge.
Paperback.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
31. LYOTARD, Jean-Francois. “The Postmodern Condition”, [After
Philosophy: End or Transformation, BAYNES, Kenneth et al Eds.], 1987.
MIT Press: Cambridge. Paperback.
32. NEWTON-SMITH, W. H. [The Rationality of Science], 1981.
Routledge and Kegan Paul: London. Paperback.
33. OGUEJIOFOR, Obi J. “How African Is Communalism?”,
[Perspectives on African Communalism, ODIMEGWU, Ike F.H. Ed.],
2007. Trafford Publishing: Canada. Paperback.
34. OLUWOLE, Sophie B. “The Africanness of a Philosophy”, [Readings
in African Philosophy: An Anthology, OLUWOLE, S.B. Ed.], 1989.
Maastech: Lagos. Paperback.
35. OZUMBA, Godfrey O. [The Philosophy of Logical Positivism and
The Growth of Science], 2001. Bacos Publishers: Calabar. Paperback.
36. POPPER, Karl R. [Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth Of
Scientific Knowledge], 1963. Routledge: London. Paperback.
37. — . [The Open Society and Its Enemies: Vol. 2 Hegel, Marx and the
Aftermath Princeton], 1963. Princeton University Press: Princeton.
Paperback.
38. — . [The Poverty of Historicism], 1957. Basic Books: New York.
Paperback.
39. RAMOSE, Mogobe B. [African Philosophy through Ubuntu],
1999/2005. Mond Books Publishers: Harare. Paperback.
40. RORTY, Richard. [Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature], 1979.
Princeton University Press: New Jersey. Paperback.
Page36
41. RUSSELL, Bertrand. [History of Western Philosophy], 1971. George
Allen and Unwin Ltd: London. Paperback.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
42. SAYER, Andrew. “Postmodernism and the Three ‘Pomo’ Flips”,
[Reason and Social Science], 2000. Sage Publications Ltd: London.
Paperback.
43. SCHEFLER, Israel. [Science and Subjectivity], 1967. Hackett
Publishers: Indianapolis. Paperback.
44. SPANOS, William. “De-struction and the Question of Postmodern
Literature: Towards a Definition”, [Par Rapport], 1979. Vol 2. No 2.
Paperback.
45. SRIWARAKUEL, Warayuth. “Process Thought and Harmony”,
[Christianity, Culture and the Contemporary World: Challenges and New
Paradigms, Alam Edward J. Ed.], 2009. Nortre Dame University Press:
Louaize, Lebanon. Paperback.
46. UNAH, Jim I. [Essays On Applied Phenomenology], 2002. Foresight
Press: Lagos. Paperback.
47. VANHOOZER, Kevin J. [Cambridge Companion to Postmodern
Theology], 2005. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge. Paperback.
Page37
Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and Religions
RELIGION, POSTMODERNISM AND POSTMODERN SCHOLARSHIP
IN AFRICA
Jacob Olu ADETOLU, MA
Department of Religious Studies
Obafemi Awolowo University Ile-Ife
Abstract
There is a somewhat agreement among the world academia and intellectuals that
the world has moved beyond the stipulated margins of modernism into what is
called the postmodern era. Consequently, postmodernism as a school of thought
has become a subject of scholastic discourse among its protagonists and
antagonists. What is done in this paper is an appraisal of postmodernism in a
broader sense and specifically postmodern scholarship in the discipline of
Religious Studies in Africa. The paper is divided into three sections: The first
section examines the postmodernism project; the second focuses on the spirit of
postmodernism within the academic study of religion with special interest in
Africa, while the third section concludes the paper by examining some criticisms
against postmodernism.
Keywords: Postmodernism, Deconstruction, Post-structuralism, Decolonization
and Modernism
Introduction
The academic discipline of religion has had a long history of scholastic ground
breaking discoveries encapsulated in the works of certain figures that have been
accorded the privilege position of ancestors as far as the academic study of
religion is concerned. Durkheim’s discourse on the nature of the sacred, Weber’s
Verstehenden methodology, Malinowski’s exploration of the distinctions
between religion and common sense and Freud’s parallel between religious
personal rituals and collective ones represent some of the foundational discourses
that constitute the root of academic study of religion and as well remain reference
points for contemporary Religious Studies scholars (GEERTZ 1973, 88). One
important issue that must be noted in this regard is that, virtually all of these
ground-breaking discoveries by these ancestors were made during the modern era
and within scholastic framework and positivist frame of mind provided by, and
characteristic of modern western thought (KUNIN 2006, 24).
Postmodernism as a scholastic phenomenon could be taken as a child of
philosophical temperament. This assertion is compatible with the fact that
Philosophy is about the only discipline that asks critical question about its
validity as a subject of enquiry. Philosophy usually questions its method, its
claim of its ability or competence to handle the task it sets before itself. These
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
philosophic dispositions are unconnected with the fact that, it is the nature of
philosophy to ask fundamental questions. In answering these questions, nothing
is accepted at its face value. Consequently, issues of whatever kind hardly get
resolved in Philosophy.
The age of enlightenment and the modern era have brought about some
level of consensus in the humans’ quest to configure the nature of their being,
their existence and of their natural environment and other phenomena with which
the human existence are inevitably interwoven. Moreover, human progress and
advancements expressed chiefly by the industrial revolution and technological
innovations seem to have suggested that, there can be some objective truth and
knowledge that could be granted consensus privilege as far as the humans’ quest
to know and to resolve his conflict is concerned. Indeed, the modern era has
recorded some progress in the evolution of universal consensus in the scientific
disciplines as well as in the humanities.
The dawn of the twentieth century seems to have reawakened
philosophical temperaments that began to question discourses across disciplines
which have reached varying levels of consensus in the human quest for
knowledge. This is the origin of what has been termed “postmodernism” of
which according to Lyotard, as discussed by Gary Aylesworth, its main goal is
the rejection of the notion that inter-subjective communication implies a set of
rules already agreed upon, and that universal consensus is the ultimate goal of
discourse (GARY 2013, 21).
The aim of this paper is to appraise postmodernism and postmodern
scholarship in Africa. This will be done in three parts. The first part will examine
the postmodernism project; the second part will focus on the spirit of
postmodernism within the academic study of religion with special interest on
Africa. The third part, which concludes the paper examines some criticisms
against postmodernism.
The Postmodernism Project
Two eras could be said to have preceded the postmodern era, the premodern and
the modern. Premodernism, which originally means “possessed by authority” (for
example, the religious authority of Catholic Church) was an age in which the
individual was dominated by tradition (MORLEY 2013, Web. N. P.). Modernism
on the other hand was birthed by the enlightenment-humanist rejection of
tradition and authority in favor of reason and natural science, grounded upon the
assumption of the autonomous individual, as the sole source of meaning and truth
within a linear conception of history of a "real" world that becomes increasingly
real and objectified (MORLEY 2013, Web. N. P.). Postmodernism can therefore
be taken as a philosophical efforts targeted at examining the nature of meaning,
knowing, and of knowledge in general even though academics in many fields
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
have debated over its precise definition. Postmodernists moreover question the
validity of the faith in science and rationalism that originated during the
Enlightenment and that became associated with the philosophy known as
modernism.
The postmodern “boundary” is not so much of the period it begins, but
more of the body of discourses that separate it from the modern era. It has been
observed that postmodernism is so diffuse to an extent that its plural form
‘postmodernisms’ would be much more correct in referring to it. Thus, it is its
somewhat fluidity and open-ended nature that makes it an epistemological model – the quality that makes it pretty difficult to define (DOLAN-HENDERSON
1996, 217). However, postmodernism has been conceived as a reaction, and
perhaps a protest against the naïve and earnest trust and confidence in progress,
and against the modern celebration and confidence in objective or scientific truth
and advancement. Specifically in philosophy, postmodernism “implies a mistrust
of the grand récits of modernity” (DOLAN-HENDERSON 1996, 217).
From the above, the postmodernism project is in its very essence,
involves the scrutinization and a somewhat rejection of the claim of modernity
embedded more or less in the justification of Western society and confidence in
progress encapsulated in the thoughts and writings of philosophical figures such
as Kant, Hegel, Marx etc., all arising from utopians visions of perfection
achieved through evolution, social progress, education and the deployment of
science (DOLAN-HENDERSON 1996, 295) Postmodernism as a term first
entered the philosophical lexicon in 1979, with the publication of [The
Postmodern Condition] by Jean-François Lyotard (GARY 2013, 1). One of the
core points in Lyotard’s postmodern discourse is his rejection of totalising
perspective on history and society, and what he referred to as historical grand
narrative exemplified in Marxism with its attempt to explain the world in terms
of patterned interrelationship (AGGER 1991, 116). In this regard, Agger opines
that Lyotard’s postmodern discourse is a clear and express rejection of Marxist
totalizing tendencies and of its political radicalism, maintaining that, it is not
possible for one to narrate a large story about the world, but a small one from a
heterogeneous point of view of a subject position (AGGER 1991, 116).
The insistence of Foucault that knowledge must not be taken to be a
phenomenon that must necessarily be accorded a privilege of unanimity, but that,
it must rather be traced to diverse and different practices and discourses within
the framework of which such body of knowledge are formulated is in line with
the view of Lyotard discussed above, and as well spelt out the goal of the
postmodern scholastic tradition. What the view of Foucault here suggests as
stated by Beatrice Skordili is that, there is no such thing as universal truth, thus,
Foucault rejects the existence of universal truth altogether (SKORDILI 2001,
337). Moreover, Foucault’s postmodern discourse on phenomena such as
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
criminality, sexuality and medicine emphasizes the idea of de-subjectification in
which sociologically speaking, the “death of the subject” will give room for a
critical interpretation of theories by the reader, and will also enable the survey
subject to become an active participant in the research (SKORDILI 2001, 337).
There are other categories of discourse that scholars usually encounter
difficulty in finely distinguishing from postmodernism. In this regard, post
structuralism and deconstruction readily come to the fore. Be that as it may,
Agger opines that, there is a serious overlap between post-structuralism and
postmodernism. Consequently, under the influence of Derrida and some French
Feminists such as Kristeva, Agger takes post-structuralism to be a theory of
knowledge and language, while following the tradition of scholars such as
Lyotard, Foucault, Barthes etc., he conceives postmodernism as a theory of
society, culture and history (AGGER 1991, 112). Derrida, one of the chief
exponents of post-structuralism, is said to be responsible for the coinage of the
term "deconstruction" which in essence means a philosophical method of looking
for weak points in modern thinking and established ways of perception (1991,
216). In sum, these three different categories of discourse, (postmodernism, post
structuralism and deconstruction) irrespective of whether scholars agreed on their
differences or not, one thing that is without dispute is that, they are all critical
response to modern scholarship.
Although, this essay is about religion and postmodern scholarship in
Africa, it is expedient we take a look at the manifestation of the postmodern
temperament in the academic study of religion in general. Friedrich Nietzsche
was a scholar whose style of thinking and writing mostly expressed in his
skepticism about the notions of truth and fact anticipated some of the central
tenets of postmodernism, such as the aesthetic attitude towards the world that
sees it as a ‘text’, the denial of facts and essences, the celebration of the plurality
of interpretations and the fragmented self, the politicization of discourse and the
downgrading of reason (BLACKBURN 1996, 262). Nietzschean skepticism
reached its peak by his pronouncement that “God is dead”, a pronouncement that
has attracted serious responses and attentions from various theologians. To some
extent, such attentions and responses have constituted the bulk of postmodern
discourse in the academic field of religion.
Thomas J. J. Altizer, a theologian, interpreted the Nietzschean
pronouncement that “God is dead” as the fullest realisation of the original, but
forgotten message of Jesus that the kingdom of God is present in the “here and
now.” (CARLSON 2001, 11). In Altizer’s view as stated by Carlson, the
postulation of God’s death is compatible with, and just as it reinforces the theist
belief in the classical transcendent and eternal God who remains beyond this
world and its history (CARLSON 2001, 11). It is through the death of God that
he was able to fully and irreversibly enter into the human historical world,
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
thereby liberating mankind from his guilty consciousness. According to Carlson,
Altizer’s reading and understanding of Nietzche is within the framework of
“Hegelian conception of kenosis and incarnation: the negation of God’s other
worldly transcendence occurs in the self-emptying through which God becomes
fully incarnated and thus immanent in this world and its history” (CARLSON
2001, 11).
Another prominent scholastic discourse of postmodernism within the
academic discipline of religion is found in the area of feminism and
ecofeminism. Susan Dolan-Henderson in this regard has identified the three
moments of postmodernism. It is necessary that the first two moments should be
discussed so that the understanding of how feminism is intricately entrenched in
postmodernism can be brought to limelight. The first moment according to her is
the postmodern critique of modernity which “consists in unmasking modernity’s
contradictory impulses and results” (DOLAN-HENDERSON 1996, 217). In
relation to this, modernity was discovered to have failed to deliver its avowed
goals and objectives. Instead of bringing to fulfillment its promises: freedom,
equality and unlimited progress, what it produced were “genocide, ecological
disaster, and multiple forms of oppression, particularly of indigenous populations
and women” (DOLAN-HENDERSON 1996, 217). The second moment in
postmodernism as identified by Dolan-Henderson is the attack of the autonomous
self by the postmodernists in which the postmodernists seek the “disappearance
of the subject"—the autonomous self of enlightenment which centered meaning
in itself, with its belief in its unlimited power and freedom which has since
remained elusive, thereby giving room for a shift from the subject to a communal
forms of meaning (DOLAN-HENDERSON 1996, 217). This shift from
subjectivity to a communal forms of meaning is significant for the feminists in
some number of ways; first, it provides the basis for the questioning of feminine
and masculine categories; second, a proper meaning for the term “woman” or
“womanhood” becomes problematic and uncertain; and lastly, there is the
possibility of an interrogation of the hitherto patriarchally produced sexual
meanings (DOLAN-HENDERSON 1996, 217). Solan-Henderson moreover
noted that, the fact that postmodernism called into question the “enlightenment
project has enabled feminist theologians to interrogate the male bias of even the
so-called liberal theologies” (1996, 217). All of the above attributes of
postmodernism in relation to feminism remains fundamental issues that continue
to give critical supports to contemporary feminists ideologies.
Religion and Postmodern Scholarship in Africa
The postmodern scholastic tradition has infiltrated itself into virtually all forms
of academic disciplines, the field of Religious Studies inclusive. Postmodernism
as an academic temperament may not be as much pronounced in other disciplines
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
as it is in the field of Philosophy. Nevertheless, there are variants of scholastic
engagements in some of these disciplines reminiscent of the postmodernist
questioning of grand récits of modernity and of the established body of
knowledge across these disciplines.
One scholar that has demonstrated this scholastic disposition in the field
of Religious Studies is Clifford Geertz. In his investigation of religion as a
cultural system, Geertz opines that the anthropological work on religion
accomplished since the Second World War, when placed side by side with the
one accomplished just before and just after the first reveals two important
shortcomings: First, the latter has made no theoretical advances over the former.
Second, it has drawn what concepts it used from a narrowly defined intellectual
tradition (1973, 87). Geertz’s observation in this regard, even though could not
be said to portray an explicit postmodern tendency, but still nevertheless remains
significant in that it pointed out a sharp distinction between two specified
scholastic epochs as far as academic study of religion is concerned. Geertz,
moreover laments the stagnation besetting the anthropological study of religion
in his day, blaming it on the production of minor variations on classical
theoretical themes (1973, 88). According to Geertz, the scholastic disposition
within the academic study of religion that favors what he refers to as “the solemn
reduplication of the achievements of accepted masters” such as Durkheim,
Weber, Freud, Malinowski etc. is the scholastic malady that has been
parochializing the thought of contemporary religious scholars (1973, 88). A
position of this nature is reminiscent of the postmodern scholarship that seeks to
critique and transcend the limitation brought about by modernism and modernist
scholars.
If there is any Continent that is in urgent need of scholastic enterprise
with which to transcend the limitation brought about by modernism, that
Continent undoubtedly would be the African Continent. This opinion is strongly
connected with the widely held belief among the African academia that the
contemporary problems facing the Continent are deeply entrenched in western
and Eurocentric ideas of modernism and colonialism. In this regard, most
contemporary scholars and thinkers of African descent are becoming the more
conscious of the danger of modernity and the need to embark on an urgent
decolonization of African scholarship and the deconstruction of certain western
paradigms clothed in the gap of Universal consensus that seems to inevitably
subjugate Africa perpetually under western control. In other, words, the view as
shared and expressed by some of these scholars is that, African scholars and
thinkers need to deconstruct certain western and Eurocentric configurations of
certain aspect of humanity for her to break away from the shackles of
underdevelopment. To some degree, this has become noticeable across the
various disciplines of humanity in recent time just as some of these scholars have
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
being demonstrating varying degree of skepticism and a general critique of
western institutions and knowledge.
For instance, Sam Aluko, in his attempt to chart a new direction towards
the development of Africa’s economy bemoans foreign economic theories
imported from the West and the quest to implement them wholly without
adapting to certain modifications that reflect the peculiarity of the African
experience (2007, 85). Noting particularly that economic theories that enhanced
and sustained economic development in Europe and America failed to do the
same in Africa, Aluko remarks:
There are no universal economic dogmas applicable at all times, to all
places, and to all economies irrespective of their respective stages of
development. Therefore, the African economists, operating in an
immature economy, must question the eternal and universal validity of
the existing economic theories. (2007, 87)
In a style and manner reminiscence of postmodern frame of mind, notable
African scholars have also embarked on the deconstruction and the
decolonization of western epistemological and institutional paradigms in the area
of culture and religion. In his essay entitled: “Rethinking Humanities Scholarship
in Africa”, Olatunji Oloruntimehin among other issues, bemoans the essence and
implication of globalization on the Continent of Africa with its uniformizing
socio-economic policies being imposed from outside by dominant powers in the
process of global governance and the consequent distortion of the civic order and
cultural values of developing countries (2007, 7). As expressed in the view of
Oloruntimehin, there are certain phenomena that make globalization a dangerous
phenomenon for the African Continent: First, there is a high level of ignorance
on the side of African political leaders and elites that globalization is “in essence
the apogee of the long process of the westernization of the world, and the implied
control of resources by a few powers, which earlier manifested in various forms
of imperialism” (2007, 6). Second, there is the place and role that have been
ascribed to science and technology in the on-going globalization process. In
support of these opinions, Oloruntimehin, citing Dennis Laurence Cuddy opines
that “science and capitalism are the two forces of contemporary society; that
science and technology has effectively taken control of the material world, while
capitalism has effectively structured it” (2007, 6). If one considers the above two
points, it would be discovered that both re-enforces one another to plunder Africa
socio-economically. From all indications, Africa does not yet have the scientific
and the technological wherewithal for heavy industrialization and the production
of certain goods in a massive manner that would make her to become major
player in the new global free-market economy. Thus, according to Martin Khor,
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
Africa has been experiencing an upsurge in inequalities of wealth and
opportunities arising from globalization and her socio-cultural conditions have
been made worse by the workings of the globalized free-market economy (2000,
1).
The way out of this menace as far as Africa is concerned calls for a
rudimentary and fundamental approaches and changes. This will enable Africa to
“cultivate knowledge of her cultural heritage, and on the basis of her
understanding of her own identity project herself and her distinctive cultures
upon other cultures of the world” (Oloruntimehin 2007, 13). To achieve this
objective, academia in Africa needs to imbibe the postmodern scholastic frame of
mind to do a rethinking and the decolonization of the existing body of knowledge
that would bequeath real socio-cultural and politico-economic freedom to Africa.
The quest to reconfigure Africa’s intellectual enterprise in order to
project and elevate her true identity free from the colonial project of the modern
era to a postmodern African identity that can place her at par with her western
counterpart is not restricted to only socio-economic and political issues alone.
There has been awareness on the side of notable African Religious Studies
scholars and Theologians of the need to decolonize and deconstruct the body of
knowledge bequeathed to Africa through colonialism if the discipline of
Religious Studies is to become the more relevant in addressing the peculiarity of
the African religious space highly embellished with the believe in the activities of
spirits and spiritual forces and other malevolent powers capable of inflicting pain
or favor on human beings. To this end, there has been what has been termed the
Theology of Decolonization. A. O. Nkwoka while quoting D. Wa Said defined
the Theology of Decolonization as “the scientific enterprise of which the main
purpose is the liberation of the wretched of the third world from spiritual-socio
politico-economic colonialism, imperialism and neocolonialism” (2007,227).
The need to decolonize the discipline of Religious Studies in general and
Biblical Studies in particular is summarily put together by Nkwoka thus: “the
development of ‘a living theology’ is indicative of the fact that Western theology
is not alive to the needs of the African theological enterprise” (2007, 229). The
abnormality that characterized the Western style of the study of religion
according to Nkwoka is that religion is approached, not as a faith, but as social
phenomenon. Thus, for him, any religion that ceases to be faith has lost its
essence as a religion, because it is the faith and spirituality of a religion that
makes it an essential social phenomenon (2007, 228). This idea with which
religion is viewed as a pure social phenomenon comes from Euro-American
thinking resulting in what Nkwoka described as “a perspective of leaving the
substance and chasing the shadow” which is a feature of post-Christian society in
which the advancements in science and technology have made religion a societal
nuisance (2007, 228).
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
It is on the basis of the above that some African Religious Studies
Scholars and Theologians in post-colonial and postmodern era are advocating the
restructuring of the curriculum of Religious Studies Departments in Nigerian
universities and the restructuring of the curriculum of theological schools to
provide for “Africanized” theology. The African world of spirit-forces has been
opined to share some affinity with the Palestinian world of the Bible. Thus,
Religious Studies in general and biblical scholarship in particular should lay
more emphasis on the spiritual side of theology rather than the intellectual and
the biblical sciences which disparage the Bible and makes it irrelevant to the
religious worldview and the lived experiences of the Africans (NKWOKA 2007,
234).
Conclusion
So far, we have been able to discuss the phenomenon of postmodernism as an
offshoot of philosophical temperament by which notable claims and
achievements of modernity have been questioned and challenged. It has also been
discussed that postmodernism as a scholastic endeavor has infiltrated itself into
all aspects of human disciplines and intellectual enterprise. Here in the Continent
of Africa, scholars in the disciplines of humanity poised with the postmodern
frame of mind have been engaging in the deconstruction of existing texts and
literatures and the decolonization of the existing body of knowledge bequeathed
to Africa through the instrumentality of colonialisms with which Africa has been
relegated to the level of an inferior race, in comparison to which her western
counterpart has be deemed superior. Be this as it may, one could assert that the
scholastic rivalry between modernist and postmodernist is totally uncalled for.
The view and the criticism of Jurgen Habermas as discussed below will suffice to
explain our point.
Habermas as discussed by Gary is regarded by most scholars as the
most prominent voice in critiquing postmodernism (GARY 2013, 20). The
criticisms of Habermas as stated by Gary against postmodernism are not directed
towards the postmodernist argumentative attack against the subject or the
autonomous self of the modern era. His critical attack against postmodernism is
more towards society and societal communicative actions (GARY 2013, 20). For
instance, Habermas, according to Gary, strategically put up, and defended
argumentative reasons that center on inter-subjective communication against the
experimental and avant-garde strategies of postmodernist scholars such as
Nietzsche, Derrida and Foucault etc., (GARY 2013, 20). The core argument of
Habermas against these scholars is entrenched in his claims that they all “commit
a performative contradiction in their critiques of modernism by employing
concepts and methods that only modern reason can provide” (GARY 2013, 20).
Thus, as it has been noted already, the modernist and postmodernist scholastic
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
dichotomy is totally uncalled for. What is needed by the human race is progress,
and it is without doubt that modernism has helped human community all over the
world in this regard. However, as the postmodernists are apt to point out,
modernism is replete with a lot of problems and contradictions. Nevertheless, the
postmodernists must also be reminded that without modernism, there cannot be
postmodernism. Postmodernism arose as scholastic quest to give a critical
appraisal to the modern era. Just as pointed out by Habermas, postmodernists all
along have been making use of the concepts and methods formulated by modern
scholars (GARY 2013, 20).” This is a sufficient ground to create a truce between
the two scholastic epochs and traditions. And this truce must first recognize the
African condition.
Relevant Literature
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
AGGER, Ben. “Critical Theory, Poststructuralism, Postmodernism:
Their Sociological Relevance”, [Annual Review of Sociology],
pp105-131, 1991. Vol. 17, Retrieved, July 2013. Web.
ALUKO, Sam. “New Directions on Scholarship in Economics in
Africa,” [Rethinking the Humanities in Africa, SOLA Akinrinade et
al Eds.], pp79-114, 2007. Obafemi Awolowo University Press: Ile
Ife. Paperback.
GARY, Aylesworth, "Postmodernism", [The Stanford Encyclopedia
of Philosophy, Edward N. Zalta Ed.], N. P. September 2005. Web.
BLACKBURN, Simon. [Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy], 1996.
Oxford University Press: New York and Oxford. Paperback.
CARLSON, Tom. “Altizer, Thomas J. J.”, [Encyclopedia of
Postmodernism, VICTOR E. Taylor and CHARLES E. Winquist
Eds.], pp10-11, 2001. Routledge: London and New York. E-book.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
11.
12.
DERRIDA, Jacques. “Deconstruction,” [A Dictionary of
Literary Terms and Literary Theory, J. A. Cuddon Ed., 3rd
edn.], Blackwell: London. Paperback.
DOLAN-HENDERSON, Susan. “Postmodernism,” [Dictionary of
Feminist Theologies, LETTY M. Russell and SHANNON J.
Clarkson Eds.], pp217-218, 1996. Westminster John Knox Press:
Kentucky. Paperback.
GEERTZ, Clifford. [The Interpretation of Cultures: Selected
Essays], 1973. Basicbooks: New York. Paperback.
KHOR, Martin. [Globalization and the South: Some Critical Issues],
2000. Spectrum Books: Ibadan. Paperback.
MORLEY, James. “Defining Postmodernism” N. P June 2012.
Retrieved June 2013. Web.
NKWOKA, A. O. “Decolonizing Christian Religious Studies and
Biblical Scholarship,” [Rethinking the Humanities in Africa, SOLA
Akinrinade et al Eds.], pp227-239, 2007. Obafemi Awolowo
University Press: Ile-Ife. Paperback.
OLORUNTIMEHIN, B. Olatunji. “Rethinking Humanities
Scholarship in Africa,” [Rethinking the Humanities in Africa, SOLA
Akinrinade et al Eds.], pp3-24, 2007. Obafemi Awolowo University
Press: Ile-Ife. Paperback.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
13.
14.
KUNIN, D. Seth. “Introduction,” [Theories of Religion: A Reader,
KUNIN, D. Seth and JONATHAN, Miles- Watson Eds.], pp1-21,
2006. Rutgers University Press: New Jersey. Paperback.
SKORDILI,
Beatrice.
“Sociology,”
[Encyclopedia
of
Postmodernism, VICTOR E. Taylor and CHARLES E. Winquist
Eds.], pp376-338, 2001. Routledge: London and New York. E-book.
Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and Religions
THE QUESTION OF OBJECTIVITY, ITS IMPLICATIONS FOR THE
SOCIAL SCIENCES IN THE ERA OF POSTMODERNISM: AFRICA IN
PERSPECTIVE
Augustine Akwu ATABOR, PhD
University of Nigeria, Nsukka
Abstract
This paper problematizes the question of objectivity as it pertains to the social
sciences. The paper accentuates the difficulty with postmodernism which tries to
deny the possibility of objective truth in the social sciences. Thus, the main
objective of this paper is to evaluate the postmodernists’ quest for relativity and
subjectivity of truth and to expose whether objectivity is attainable in the social
sciences in the same way it is attainable in the natural sciences. This paper
upholds that objectivity in the social science is important in working out a
holistic global ideology, and since this global ideology hopes to provide for and
project justice and respect for persons and communities as well as provide a basis
for the minimizing and resolving of conflicts locally and internationally, Africa
can on this grounds dare to be part of this global project without fear of playing a
“western script” called globalization.
Keywords: Modernism, postmodernism, Social Science, Hermeneutics,
Objectivity
Introduction
The postmodern controversy of objectivity in the social sciences raises questions
that pertain to the deepest dimensions of our being and humanity: how we know
what we know, how we should think about individual endeavor and collective
aspirations, whether progress is meaningful and how it should be sought. Post
modernism questions causality, determinism, egalitarianism, humanism, liberal
democracy, necessity, objectivity, rationality, responsibility and truth. It takes on
issues that are profoundly fundamental for the future of social science
(ROSENAU 1992, 1). The emergence of post-modernism may simply reflect
intellectual currents in the larger society, but in the social sciences it also reacts
to uncritical confidence in modern science and smugness about objective
knowledge.
Historically, science attacked the arbitrary authority of church and
monarchy, both of which based their legitimacy on theology. Modern science
established its reputation on objectivity, rigorous procedures of inquiry, the
material rather than the metaphysical. Science, in turn, came to claim its own
monopoly of truth. Its authority expanded and superseded that held by its more
“irrational and arbitrary” antecedents (ROSENAU 1996, 9). Post-modernists call
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
to question the rational base of this monopoly of truth ascribed to the sciences
and are uneasy with their more conventional colleague's uncritical acceptance of
philosophical foundationalism, the Enlightenment heritage, and the
methodological suppositions of modern science.
Postmodernism haunts social science today in a number of respects,
some plausible and some preposterous, post-modern approaches dispute the
underlying assumptions of mainstream social science and its research product
over the last three decades. The challenges post-modernism poses seem endless.
It rejects epistemological assumptions, refutes methodological conventions,
resists knowledge claims, obscures all versions of truth, and dismisses policy
recommendations (ROSENAU 1996, 3). Post-modernism represents the coming
together of elements from a number of different, often conflicting orientations. It
appropriates, transforms, and transcends French structuralism, romanticism,
phenomenology, nihilism, populism, existentialism, hermeneutics, Western
Marxism, Critical Theory, and anarchism. Although post-modernism shares
elements with each, it has important quarrels with every approach (ROSENAU
1996, 13).
It is against this background that this paper is out to argue that the social
sciences have a right claim to objectivity and that they have much to offer in the
endless struggle to enhance the human condition. Thus, it is important to explore
the postmodern perspective of the social sciences and to critically evaluate their
claims as this would build a fertile ground upon which Africa can be part of the
global ideology for justice, peace and fairness. However, let us first clarify some
important terms to make the objectives of this paper more explicit.
Postmodernism
Postmodernism according to Eva Brann can be deconstructed in a tripartite
fashion; Post-modern-ism. Its first syllable, "post", does not mean simply "after"
in time, as period prefixes often do. The "post" in this term, says Lyotard, one of
the leading definers of the movement, intends the Greek preposition “ana,”
which as a prefix can mean "back again," as in anamnesis, - re-collection.
Recollection is not mere recall, but effective re-appropriation of memory (1992,
5). Lyotard goes further to say; "The postmodern would have to be understood
according to the paradox of the future (post) anterior (modo)" (BRANN 1992, 5).
He means that in a postmodern work, the future comes "after" the "just now" in
the sense that; such a work is not composed in accordance with any previous
universal rules, or, as he calls it, any “metanarrative.” It has no antecedently
present conditions. He views postmodernism as incredulity toward
metanarratives. This definition is made with reference to the term "modern"
which designates "any science that legitimates itself with reference to a meta
discourse, such as, the dialectics of spirit, the hermeneutics of meaning," or, I
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
might add, the shared rationality of minds. Thus, the "post" makes reference both
to the readmission of history by anamnesis and to the definitive exclusion of
metaphysics and its derivatives. The sawing through of the perch we sit on, the
undermining of the structures we rely on, is to be taken in the most total sense;
“Nothing is to support anything” (BRANN 1992, 6).
The second element, "modern," is a coinage of the sixth century (AD). It
comes from the Latin word modo, meaning "just now” or “this moment." It is a
word needed, now as then, when an epoch is felt to have been superseded by the
present, the up-to-date. It betokens a sense of having left something behind and
of being on the cutting edge of time. It is a term of temporal self-location. There
have been many modernisms: theological, national, aesthetic, literary,
architectural. In fact, one might say that modernity is the propensity to
modernisms; I mean the urge of elites not only to be continually displacing the
late by the latest, but to induce "movements" that is, a tendentious drift, in
followers (BRANN 1992, 4).
The final element is the “ism" or the personal form "ist." It is a Greek
and Latin ending, connoting the adoption, often perverse or specious, of the
habits of a group. For example, barbarism is a behavior like that of those who
babble inarticulately, and a sophist is one who looks like a wise man, a sophas,
without having or loving wisdom, in opposition to a philosophos. Whether for
good or ill, "ism" connotes running in droves, and an 'ist’ is an intellectual
assimilationist (BRANN 1992, 4).
Having done this tripartite deconstruction, what then is postmodernism?
According to Terry Eagleton, postmodernism is “a style of thought which is
suspicious of classical notions of truth, reason, identity and objectivity, of single
frameworks, grand narratives or ultimate grounds of explanation” (1996, vii.).
Thus, from this definition, it could be sustained that; postmodernism is a drive
towards some form of relativism or subjectivism. A movement that is out to
question every convention and tradition and most importantly for this paper, it is
a movement that questions the grounds of the social sciences’ claim for
objectivity. As a reaction on modernism, postmodernism emerged in academic
studies in the mid-80’s of last century. It can be seen as a worldview that
emphasizes the existence of different worldviews and concepts of reality, rather
than one ‘correct’ or ‘true’ one. Whereas modernism emphasized a trust in the
empirical scientific method, and a distrust and lack of faith in ideologies and
religious beliefs that could not be tested using scientific methods, postmodernism
emphasizes that a particular reality is a social construction by a specific group,
community or class of persons.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
The Social Sciences
Social science is a group of academic discipline that examines society and how
people interact and develop as a culture. Social science as a field of study is
separate from the natural sciences, which covers topics such as physics and
chemistry. Social science as an academic field of study, developed out of the age
of enlightenment as individuals began to take a more disciplined approach to
quantifying their observations of society. Over time, similar aspects of the
society, such as communication, were separated into unique fields of study.
Objectivity
Diana Mertz views objectivity as a method of acquiring knowledge by reasoning
solely based on the facts of reality and in accordance with the laws of logic
(2013, Web. N. P.). Objectivity is a central philosophical concept related to
reality and truth which has been variously defined by sources. Generally,
objectivity means the state or quality of being true even outside of a subject’s
individual feelings, imaginings or interpretations. A proposition is generally
considered to be objectively true (to have objective truth) when its truth condition
are met and are “mind-independent” – that is, existing freely or independently
from a mind (from the thoughts, feelings, ideas etc. of a sentient subject). In a
simpler meaning of the term, objectivity refers to the ability to judge fairly
without bias or external influence that occurs in a phenomenological way (Web,
N. P.).
Historical Origins of Postmodernism
The post-modern turn is not native to North America; rather, it is an adopted
child of continental Europe, predominantly of French and German descent. As
one important French intellectual smugly points out, post-modernism and post
structuralism sell as well in the North American intellectual market as
“Beaujolais Nouveau.” The irony is that, although the French get most of the
credit for developing post-modernism, German philosophers, mainly Nietzsche
and Heidegger, inspired it. Despite this intellectual debt, contemporary German
philosophers, especially Jürgen Habermas, are among post-modernism's most
severe critics. But post-modernism is not always received so sympathetically in
France either. Important French post-modernists, particularly Jacques Derrida,
have of late lost credibility in their own country. Nevertheless the appeal of post
modernism continues to grow outside France (ROSENAU 1992, 12).
Postmodernism emerged from the existentialist and phenomenologist
philosophies of, amongst others, Nietzsche, Heidegger and Husserl. It is
unsurprising, then, that it has many features in common with social
phenomenology and ethnomethodology, which share some of the same
philosophical precursors. While these approaches were more methodologically
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
inclined than postmodernism, they similarly rejected the Enlightenment attempt
to create universal knowledge, preferring to emphasis subjective meaning and to
problematize everyday occurrences (AGGER 2013, 117).
Affirmative and Skeptical postmodernism
The divergent, even contradictory expositions of post-modernism underline the
need to distinguish among its various orientations, if we are ever to be able to
talk about it at all. There are probably as many forms of post-modernisms as
there are post-modernists (FEATHERSTONE 1998, 207). If it were not so
clumsy, we could speak of post-modernisms. But, within this diversity of post
modern pronouncements, as far as the social sciences are concerned, two broad,
general orientations, the skeptical post-modernists and the affirmative post
modernists, can be delineated (ROSENAU 1992, 15).
Inspired by Continental European philosophies, especially Heidegger and
Nietzsche, skeptical postmodernism is the dark side of postmodernism, the
postmodernism of despair, the postmodernism that speaks of the immediacy of
death, the demise of the subject, the end of the author, the impossibility of truth,
and the abrogation of the Order of Representation. Post-modernists of this
orientation, adopt a blasé attitude, as if "they have seen it all" and concluded that;
nothing really new is possible (GITLIN 1989, 103). The skeptical post
modernism (or merely skeptics), offering a pessimistic, negative, gloomy
assessment, argue that; the post-modern age is one of fragmentation,
disintegration, malaise, meaninglessness, vagueness or even absence of moral
parameters and societal chaos (SCHERPE 1986, 101).
According to Rosenau, the affirmative postmodernism which is more
indigenous to Anglo-North American culture than to Europe, has a more general
optimistic view of the post-modern age. The generally optimistic affirmatives are
oriented toward process. They are either open to positive political action
(struggle and resistance) or content with the recognition of visionary, celebratory
personal non-dogmatic projects that range from New Age religion to new wave
life-styles and include a whole spectrum of post-modern social movements. Most
affirmatives seek a philosophical and ontological intellectual practice that is non
dogmatic, tentative, and non-ideological (ROSENAU 1992, 15).
The Social Studies as a Science and the Question of Objectivity
To be scientific would entail a level of systematic and disciplined method of
enquiring knowledge and that knowledge must be a verifiable knowledge. This
brings to fore the question; whether the society, its institutions and relationships
are susceptible to scientific study? Allusions to the fact that the terms "social"
and "scientific" may not sit comfortably together, was illustrated by the decision
of the British Government in the early nineteen eighties to change the name of
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
the Social Science Research Council (which included mass communication
research in its remit) to the Economic and Social Research Council. The message
seemed to be: if it is social, it can't be scientific" (HALLORAN 1998). However,
this position remains a point of debate as other persons are ready to classify both
the natural and social sciences in terms of methodology under the unity of
scientific method.
The achievements of the natural sciences in the wake of the scientific
revolution of the seventeenth Century have been most impressive. Their
investigation of nature has produced elegant and powerful theories that have not
only greatly enhanced understanding of the natural world, but also increased
human power and control over it. Modern physics for instance, has shed light on
such mysteries as the origin of the universe and the source of the sun’s energy,
and it has also spawned technology that has led to supercomputers, nuclear
energy (and bombs), and space exploration. Natural science is manifestly
progressive, insofar as, over time its theories tend to increase in- depth, range and
predictive power. It is also consensual, that is, there is a general agreement
among Natural Scientists regarding what the aims of science are and how to
conduct it, including how to evaluate theories. At least, in the long run, Natural
Science tends to produce consent regarding which theories are valid. Given this
evident success, many philosophers and social theorists have been eager to
import the methods of Natural Science to the study of the social world. If social
science were to achieve the explanatory and predictive power of Natural Science,
it could help solve vexing social problems, such as violence and poverty,
improve the performance of institutions and generally foster human well-being.
Those who believe that adapting the aims and methods of Natural Science to
social inquiry is both possible and desirable, support the unity of scientific
method. Such advocacy in this context is also referred to as naturalism. Of
course, the effort to unify social and natural science requires reaching some
agreement on what the aims and methods of science are (or should be). A school
of thought, broadly known as positivism, has been particularly important here.
Despite the collapse of positivism as a philosophical movement, it continues to
exercise influence on contemporary advocates of the unity of scientific method.
(GORTON 2013, Web N. P.).
However, it must be known that postmodernism has a lot of issues with
positivism and the postmodernists’ criticisms of positivism has its implications
for the social sciences, at least on the question of objectivity. This is so because if
the social sciences were only to be objective when the methods of the natural
sciences are imported into its modes of inquiry, then the attack of postmodernism
on positivism is an attack aimed at the possible claims of objectivity by the social
science.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
It is a fact that many social scientists are driven to often rely implicitly
upon the positivists’ tenets that experience is the basis of knowledge and it is
possible to reflect the world objectively, without relying upon philosophical and
theoretical assumptions. The use of ‘positivistic attitude’ here refers to
approaches that involve any of these suppositions: that the methods of the natural
sciences may be directly adapted for the social sciences; that the role of the
political analyst is that of an impartial observer of social reality; that the goal of
political analysis is to formulate law-like generalizations; that knowledge and
language are purely instrumental.
Postmodernism has done much to challenge this positivistic attitude in
the social sciences. Michel Foucault, a key postmodern thinker (although he
rejected the label), is noted for his appraisal of the social sciences. He dismissed
social scientists’ claims to objectivity and neutrality by showing how they
conflated moral and legal norms into scientific truth. For example, Foucault
asserted that crime was judged against a scientific ‘knowledge’ of what was
normal, and that punishment had come to be legitimated as much by social
science as by the legal system. Deviations from the law came to be seen as
offences against ‘objectively’ known human nature (AMERY 2008, 6).
According to Amery, Foucault specifically expanded Nietzschean
historic philosophy in order to question beliefs and aspects of everyday life –
such as madness or sexuality – thought to be timeless. Through this technique of
‘genealogy’ he was able to trace the development of present-day institutions and
ideas and to show that they were grounded in history rather than the ahistorical
notions of Reason and Truth. For example, Foucault argues that the modern
experience of madness, rather than being grounded in unchanging scientific fact,
has its roots in the ‘Great Confinement’ of the seventeenth century, when
‘unreasonable’ members of the society were placed in asylums (2008, 6).
Jacques Derrida, although he differed from Foucault in important ways,
advanced an equally significant critique of positivism. To Derrida, all discourses,
including supposedly scientific reports, rely on concealed assumptions and
cannot be understood without them. (AGGER 2013, 112). As with Foucault,
these texts also present a certain view of the world as objective truth. Thus,
traditional status-attainment research which defined social mobility in terms of
the occupational status of one’s father was far from neutral: it presented a view of
the social world where only men worked or should work, and in fact
misrepresented reality by ignoring women who worked. (AGGER 2013, 113)
Derrida pioneered the technique of ‘deconstruction’ in order to expose the hidden
assumptions of texts.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
Postmodernism, the Social Science and the Politics of Globalization
The term Globalization could mean different thing to different people. For some,
globalization entails the Westernization of the world, while for others it involves
a cover for the ascendancy of capitalism. Some see globalization as generating
increasing homogeneity, while others see it producing diversity and
heterogeneity through increased hybridization. For business, globalization is a
strategy for increasing corporate profits and power, for government it is often
deployed to promote an increase in state power, while non-government social
organizations see globalization as a lever to produce positive social goods like
environmental action, democratization, or humanization. Many theorists equate
globalization with modernity, while others claim that the "global age" follows
and is distinctly different from the "modern age." Indeed, for some theorists, we
live in a global age or epoch, in which globalization is the defining concept,
while others find claims for the novelty and centrality of globalization
exaggerated.
Though, one cannot claim ignorance of the politicization of
globalization, however, the need for the world to have a global ideology that
would provide for and project justice and respect for persons and communities as
well as provide a basis for the minimizing and resolving of conflicts locally and
internationally has become increasingly clear. While it is believed that the social
sciences will provide the framework and grounds to achieve this objective, the
postmodernists’ attack on the plausibility of the claims of objectivity by the
social sciences, remains a big challenge.
Postmodernists have highlighted how much political theory and research
ignores or relegates certain social groups to the sidelines, furthering their
disempowerment. All theories, they argue, come from a particular standpoint,
and in the Western world, the dominant standpoint has often been that of a white,
heterosexual man. As demonstrated above, these theories have the power to
present their views of the world as scientific truth, and thus legitimate a social
and political order where certain groups are marginalized or oppressed (AMERY
2008, 7). According to Foucault, the state works hand in hand with other
institutions of the modern world – prisons, schools, medical clinics and the
military – to monitor and control people. It accomplishes this, however, neither
principally through brute force nor via a regiment of rewards and punishments.
Rather, the state works in concert with social science to construct the very
categories through which individuals understand themselves. In doing so, it
establishes the criteria by which normal and abnormal behavior is understood,
and thereby regulates behavior, most importantly, by getting people to regulate
themselves. In this way, social science has in effect become a handmaid to the
forces of domination rather than a potential source of emancipation.
Significantly, Foucault never claimed that this new type of control is intentional.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
It is merely an unwelcomed artifact of social science. (GORTON 2013, Web. N.
P.).
Thus, while Modernism was Universalist in outlook, much of its
universalism was the universalization and the projection of the values/ideology of
a particular class, ethnic group or culture and this constitutes one of the major
critique of modernism by postmodernists; who pointed out that the creation of
ideas, truth and knowledge are context-based and confined to contexts. It is in
this regard that we bring in the perspective of Africa in this paper. How much of
African life-world is represented in the so-called global matrix of modernity?
The evident absence of the African perspective in the modern dynamics readily
makes the postmodern ideology an attraction for the African intelligentsia.
Postmodernism is deeply relativist; it undermines universalism; and, is itself
unable to provide a common frame of reference that will help in solving the
world’s problems such as violence and conflicts, the integration of peripheral
economics into the global economy but it at least, demolishes modernity which
seeks to impose the culture of a determined race on the rest of humanity which
includes Africa.
Africa and Globalization
It is not for no reason that the African man is suspicious of the idea of
globalization which is one of the features of the postmodern era. According to
Ike Obiora, Africa has experienced globalization in four phases; the first stage
which has to do with slavery, robbed the continent of some of its citizens, at the
second stage, colonialism came with its exploitative and divisive alien patterns,
at the third stage is the experience of neo-colonial political pressures and
economic forces that set trade patterns, investment policies, debt arrangement
and others, the fourth stage is what is rather branded today as globalization
(2014, 23). All this, have contributed in painting the idea of globalization
wrongly, hence the painful African memory. It is a fact that with the rate of
technological advancement in the world, the world has rather become a global
family. The reality of this development has made it important that there be global
ideologies that govern human rights and actions. However, as important as this
may sound, Africa has come to believe that there is always a western agenda that
is being preached in the name of globalization, though this is not without some
element of truth, this paper has tried to show that with findings garnered from the
social science regarding those basic and common concerns of humanity, a global
ideology could be arrived at. This version of globalization, it is hoped would be
inclusive rather than exclusive of some cultures as the modern global matrix had
done. It may therefore be assumed that the difficulty of arriving at objectivity and
a truly universal truth was due to the lopsided nature of the modern global
matrix. In a postmodern era, where relative conception of truth is imperative and
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
a culture-based objectivity clearly inevitable, it remains not just a possibility but
a practical expectation that cross-cultural reasoning would pave the way and
create interlinking corridors across cultures. These shall be the areas of common
grounds pertaining to the universal agreement of human reason. Thus, even in the
relativity and culture-based objectivity of postmodernism, there may be room
even in the social sciences for a form universal objectivity and truth.
Conclusion
It is my contention that though all-round objectivity in the social science is
difficult, aiming at it, or attaining as much of it as reasonably possible, is a
necessary condition for the conduct of all scientific inquiry. Why should we
consider complete objectivity so important that we should pursue it even when
admitting it to be somehow inaccessible? In my opinion, viewing inquiry as
subjective, or as an entirely individual matter, would be the exclusion of all
criticism; and this would be the exclusion of rational debate; and the exclusion of
some cultures like Africa; and this would also be the denial of the thesis of the
intellectual or rational unity of mankind. It thus opens the door to irrationalism
and elitism, whether social or racial.
It is ordinarily expected that no matter the diversities in terms of race,
nationality, ethnicity, culture and language among men, there will remain to be
some common grounds of our shared humanity. Furthermore, it is becoming
increasingly clear that it is necessary for the world to have a global ideology that
would provide for and project justice and respect for persons and communities as
well as provide a basis for the minimizing and resolving of conflicts locally and
internationally. It is hoped that within the quest for this objective, Africa will not
be marginalized either directly or indirectly.
Relevant Literatures
1. AGGER, Ben. “Critical Theory, Post Structuralism,
Postmodernism: Their Sociological Relevance,” [Annual Review
of Sociology], Pp.105-31, 1991. Retrieved. 2013. No 17. Web.
2. AMERY, Frann. “Allowing the Other to Speak: The Relevance of
Postmodernism to Political analysis”, [Reinvention: An
International Journal of Undergraduate Research], Web, N. P.,
2008. Vol. 1, Issue 2. Retrieved, August, 2014. Web.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
3. BRANN, Eva. “What is Postmodernism?”, [Harvard Review of
Philosophy]. Pp.1-10, spring, 1992. Retrieved, July, 2014. Web.
4. EAGLETON, Terry. [The Illusions of Postmodernism], 1996.
Blackwell Publishers: Oxford. E-book.
5. FEATHERSTONE, Mike. “In Pursuit of the Postmodern: An
Introduction,” [Theory, Culture and Society]. Pp.195-207,
June,1998. Vol. 5. No. 2. Retrieved July 2014.Web.
6. GORTON, William. “Philosophy of the Social Sciences”, [Internet
Encyclopedia of Philosophy], Web, N. P, N. D. Retrieved 26th
July, 2013. Web.
7. GITLIN, Todd. “Postmodernism: Roots and Politics”, [Dissent],
Pp.100-108, winter, Jul/Aug 1989. Retrieved July, 2014. Web.
8. HALLORAN, J. D, “Social Sciences, Communication Research
and the Third World,” [Media Development], 1998. Vol. 2,
WACC. Retrieved July, 2014. Web.
9. HSIEH, Diana. “What is Objectivity?”, [Find Enlightenment],
June 1999. Retrieved July 26th, 2013. Web.
10. OBIORA, Ike and EDOZIEN, Ndidi Nnoli. “Africa in the Age of
Globalization: The Challenges of Culture Identity in an
interdependent World,” [Globalization and African Self
Determination: What is the Future? OBIORA, Ike Ed]. Pp.21-28,
2014. Catholic Institute for Development, Justice and Peace
printing and Publishing House: Uwani, Enugu. Paperback.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
11. ROSENAU, Pauline. [Postmodernism and the Social Sciences:
Insights, Inroads and Intrusions], 1992. Princeton University Press:
Princeton. E-book.
12. SCHERPE, Klaus. “Dramatization and De-dramatization of the
End: The Apocalyptic Consciousness of Modernity and
Postmodernity”, [Cultural Critique], Pp.95-129, winter 1986-87.
No.5. Retrieved July 2014. Web.
Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and Religions
THE CULTURE-ORIENTED BIAS OF AFRICAN PHILOSOPHICAL
INQUIRY
David A. OYEDOLA, MA
Department of Philosophy
Obafemi Awolowo University
Ile-Ife, Nigeria
Abstract
African philosophers with Levy Bruhlian disposition like Appiah, Masolo, and
Wiredu posit that African philosophy is culture-biased. Some other African
philosophers like Nkrumah, Janz, Hountondji, and Makinde assert that Africa’s
precolonial indigenous culture is ahistorical and the dependence of
contemporary African philosophy on culture cannot be de-emphasized.
However, these views, though opposing, undermine two things; the way African
philosophy has chosen to divulge itself and the objectivity that is peculiar to
African philosophy. Nevertheless, this study concedes that if by implication,
what these views are saying is that African philosophy will have to sink because
it is culture-biased; then, this study insists that any other philosophy (e.g.,
European philosophy) would have to sink. Precisely, there is no difference
between any of the philosophies with respect to the fact that the interests of the
European philosopher determine what he selects for investigation, just like what
an African philosopher chooses to investigate and it is safe to speculate that
these interests whether in the West or in Africa are culture-colored.
Keywords: African philosophy, European philosophy, Culture, Bias, Inquiry
Introduction
This study represents a departure from the Levy Bruhlian disposition where
anthropology (the new science that replaced the old science of subject-object
dichotomy, i.e., epistemology) became the tool for questioning the ratiocination
of the “Other” (e.g., Africans). Furthermore, this study attempts to depart from
another disposition which relegates African cultural inquiry or nullifies the
identity of the Africans. The philosophers under the latter disposition include
the likes of Kwame Appiah (Illusions of Race, 1992; Color Conscious: The
Political Morality of Race, 1996; The Ethics of Identity, 2005; and
Cosmopolitanism: Ethics in the World of Strangers, 2006) and Dismas A.
Masolo (African Philosophy and the Post-colonial: The Misleading Abstractions
about Identity, 1997). The Levy Bruhlian disposition posits that Africans, south
of Sahara, lack the property of ratiocination, it further helps in dictating the
mind and writings of many traditional, contemporary and academic Africans in
Africa, the diaspora and some other African philosophers. However, Levy
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
Bruhl’s view, for Kwasi Wiredu, Odera Oruka, Olusegun Oladipo, Moses
Makinde, Didier Kaphagawani, Barry Hallen, Peter Bodunrin, Paulin
Hountondji, Placid Tempels, Moses Oke, Barry Hallen, Frantz Fanon, Robin
Horton, Amilcar Cabral, and host of others, has dire implications on the post
colonial identity of Africa, Africans and African philosophy. Appiah and
Masolo are of African origin but they have used their analytic training to nullify
racial and identity concerns in their discourses. This nullification by Appiah and
Masolo confirms the position that racial-identity, for Africans, is impossible.
Their reason is because there is just one race; the human race. Thus, the post
colonial quest of Africa, Africans and African philosophy to have an
independent racial identity has been put to rest because this quest has no greater
importance than the global ‘human race’ (APPIAH 1992, 1996, 2005, 2006 and
MASOLO 1997). For African philosophy to reclaim its stand, the ability to have
something to profess in order to convince others needs urgency. Similarly, the
postcolonial perception or impression that Africa (coupled with African
philosophy) is not inferior needs to be proven. Thus, the post Levy-Bruhlian
perception which persistently receives its support from some post-colonial
professional or European trained Africans sees African philosophy as a field that
confronts a certain difficulty; this difficulty is that it is culture-bias or tradition
oriented. In resolving this problem, some African philosophers like Olusegun
Oladipo (2002, 233), Moses Oke (2006, 337), Kwame Nkrumah (1974, 20),
Odera Oruka (1991, 177), Peter Kanyandago (2003, 31-33), etc., have
emphasized the need for historical retrospection in re-making a new Africa;
while, some others like Bruce Janz (2003, 32), Kwasi Wiredu (1998, 195),
Messay Kebede (2004, 129), Richard Bell (2002, 198), etc., maintain that
contemporary African philosophy has come of age (no longer culture
dependent); while some others like Moses Makinde (2010, 28-29), Didier
Kaphagawani (1998, 86-87), Tsenay Serequeberhan (1998, 12), Niyi Osundare
(1998, 29), etc., have postulated that Africa’s precolonial indigenous culture
cannot help in reigniting Africa’s development, and that the training of
professional African philosophers would aid a new modality of doing African
philosophy.
Given that African philosophy needs to be re-assessed or rescued, the
fundamental problem that it is culture-biased cannot be ignored. Since the
culture-bias has become a plate upon which African philosophy is viewed, this
study concedes that there cannot be a sufficient explication or defence that
European philosophy, or any other philosophy, is not culture-bias too.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
Culture-Bias and Culture-Neutrality: The Nature of African and European
Cultural
Investigations
It is pertinent we turn, finally, to the difficulty that can be said to be confronting
African philosophy because the culture to which we can say that the
philosophers in African philosophy are committed not only colors the contents
of their findings but also controls the assessment of the evidence on which they
base their conclusion. Since African philosophers generally differ in their
culture orientations, the “culture neutrality” that appears to be so pervasive in
the European philosophy is therefore often held to be impossible in African
philosophy. In the judgment of many European anthropologists, or some
Western-trained professional African philosophers, it is accordingly absurd to
expect African philosophy to exhibit the unanimity so common among
philosophers in European philosophical history concerning what ought to
constitute the problematic issues to be discussed in philosophy, the analytic
methodology to be used, and the satisfactory explanations that are least expected
of them. Let us examine some of the grounds that have been put forward for this
contention. It will be easy to distinguish four groups of such reasons, so that our
discussion will deal in turn with the asserted role of cultures
in (a) the selection of difficulties, (b) the ascertainment of the profundity of their
outcomes, (c) the approval of cultural facts, and (d) the appraisal of evidence.
The Selection of Difficulties
The reason, perhaps most frequently cited, is the fact that the things an African
philosopher selects for investigation are determined by his own conception of
what are culturally important values. According to one influential view, for
instance, African philosopher deals with materials to which he attributes
“cultural importance, consequence, or meaning,” so that a “cultural-orientation”
is inherent in his choice of material for investigation. John Ezeugwu’s point that
“it is not bad for the Africans to defend their philosophy and their origin, as
against the claims and positions of the few African thinkers, who do not believe
that African philosophy exists, and a great number of the Westerners who see
nothing meaningful in their thoughts and ideas, but in doing so, they became
biased and elevated their philosophy and relegated other philosophies to the
background” (2014, 41), could not have been made in passing without a specific
aim to resolve certain problems, whether those problems are derivative of some
Africans or European anthropologists. Though, Ezeugwu could not have meant
that African cultural inquirers have been prejudiced because they are cultural
beings, yet he provided a classic statement which is calm, judicious and
prescient. In his work, A Short History of African Philosophy, Barry Hallen,
though, is a vigorous proponent of the view that “philosophy in any cultural
context is not likely to be the easiest subject in the world,” (2002, 1), however,
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
its presentation can make it seem excessively technical and obscure in nature,
and can frustrate understanding unnecessarily. This suggests that both
philosophies (African and European philosophies) are situated in the culture
which colours the contents of any of the findings on which their adherents base
the conclusions of their different works.
The implication of John Ezeugwu and Barry Hallen’s views can be said
to be based on the cultural or contextual view of how philosophy in Africa has
come to be distinct, and the way that it can be understood which may make the
meaning of the terms used and the analysis to be technically obscure. African
philosophy can sometimes be understood in the way some influential Anglo
trained African professional philosophers like Kwasi Wiredu (How Not to
Compare African Thought with Western Thought, 1998), Barry Hallen (A Short
History of African Philosophy, 2002), Lucius Outlaw (African, African
American, Africana Philosophy, 1998), Tsenay Serequeberhan (The Critique of
Eurocentrism and the Practice of African Philosophy, 1997), Chukwudi Eze
(Modern Western Philosophy and African Colonialism, 1998), Aime Cesaire
(Discourse On Colonialism, 1997), Frantz Fanon (Racism and Culture, 1997,
The Wretched of the Earth, 1997), Stephen Biko (The Definition of Black
Consciousness, 1998) etc., have opined that African culture-laden discourse
differs from its Western counterpart. Their view is that African philosophy
should transcend the culture-laden discourse to develop the analytic and critical
tendencies so as to compete meaningfully in the global philosophical discourse.
However, he (Barry Hallen) have painted the notion that philosophy does not
necessarily have to be analytic, rigorous and critical – he nevertheless argued
that “the explanation I (Barry Hallen) can offer is that African philosophy
should pay particular attention to a limited number of themes in Africa, so that
they are deliberately isolated, and that they are extracted from their broader
contexts, in order to facilitate relevant comparisons” (2002, 1). The perception
of the meaningfulness of culture to us is the presupposition of its becoming an
object of investigation for an African philosopher or investigator.
It is well-nigh self-evident to say that African philosophers, like
philosophers in Europe or America, do not investigate everything, but direct
their attention to certain selected portions of the inexhaustible content of
concrete African reality. In addressing an aspect of this reality, Fanos
Mangena‘s perception is that “for many years African philosophy has not been
taken seriously by both Africans and Western philosophers alike. African
philosophy has been disparaged and downgraded for failing to have, among
other things, a coherent system of thought and a method that can be applied
across the cultures of this world” (2014, 96). If we are to take Fanos Mangena
very serious, his objective that “African philosophers should develop a system
that is coherent and that can be applied world over, i.e., a logic on which
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
African philosophy should sit instead of running away from their burning house
only to refuge next door” (2014, 96), would mean one thing: the African ethno
philosophical approach to the body philosophy would become the black or
African extraction which the Africans can be proud of. However, the problem
that he (Mangena) may need to address is whether logic is divisible, where
African logic, American logic, Asian logic, Arab logic, European continental
logic, European analytic logic, etc., become possible. From the rules of modus
ponens (MP), modus tolens (MT), repetition (R), double negation (DN), etc., it
is perceivable that logic is logic, just as mathematics is mathematics, and that
logic is not divisible into different cultures and continents. Its rules and methods
are not culture-dependent. Given this problem, how can Fanos Mangena be
rescued? The usage of the word ‘logic’ may not mean logic as a discourse of
reasoning that follow rules but like a cultural way of life that people or outsiders
can call the African way or rules of reference or inference. With this, Mangena’s
view that there is the need for a logic on which African philosophy should sit is
admissible and relevant.
Moreover, let us accept the thesis, if only for the sake of the argument,
that an African philosopher addresses himself exclusively to matters which he
believes are important because of their relevance to his cultural-based values. It
is not clear, in a way, why the fact that an investigator selects the materials he
studies in the light of problems which interest him, and which seem to him to
bear on matters he regards as important, is of greater moment for the logic of
African inquiry than it is for the other branch of inquiry outside Africa. The
things that an African philosopher selects for study with a view to determining
the conditions or consequences of their existence may indeed be dependent on
the indisputable fact that he is a cultural being.
In short, there is no difference between any of the philosophical
dispositions (be it African or European) with respect to the fact that the interests
of an African philosopher determine what he selects for investigation. But this
fact represents no obstacle to the successful pursuit of objectively controlled
inquiry in any branch of study or within each branch of study. For example, an
African social and political philosopher may be interested in the nature of
election rigging, or an African philosopher may be interested in the spiritual
bond between twins and the effects it has on the immediate family and
environment, while an American philosopher may be interested in the reason
why the food that teenagers eat causes obesity. This does not presuppose any
means of relative culturality, but it presupposes the view that there exists in each
disposition an iota of objectivity which may not need to overlap or be found
synonymous.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
The Ascertainment of the Profundity of their Outcomes
A more substantial reason commonly given for the culture-oriented character of
African philosophy is that, since an African philosopher is himself affected by
considerations of right and wrong in the particular African culture or in the
African subject that he is investigating, his own notion of what constitutes a
satisfactory African order and his own standard of personal and African form of
philosophical disposition enter, in point of fact, into the analyses of African
phenomena. In this respect, the veracity of the truth of African philosophy must
be judged by admittedly “relative standards, i.e., in terms of the ends sought or
the standards employed by the African society or philosopher concerned, rather
than in terms of the European or American philosopher’s own criteria. Ernest
Nagel’s description that, “yet, the history of human thought has led not to one
philosophy but to several” (1968, 100), implies that the cultural attitudes
implicit in the African ways of thinking will differ from that of its European
counterpart, and sometimes conflict. The reason why there may be conflict
between African and European dispositions of what should constitute a
philosophical objectivity rests on, (i) the presupposition that there exist
differences in what they portend and potentate. An implication can be derived
here; what the African philosopher selects for investigation will remain relative
to his culture. The same is applicable for European or American philosopher;
and, (ii) they (African and European philosophers) sought to achieve the ‘end’
by the means possible or through different criteria. Thus, there are basic
judgments which we cannot do without in African philosophy, and which
clearly do not express a purely personal philosophy of the enquirer or African
values arbitrarily assumed. Rather, what African philosophers select for
investigation grow out of the history of thought in Africa, from which the
anthropologist of European descent can seclude himself as little as can anyone
else.
It has often been noted that the study of African phenomena receives
much of its impetus from a strong moral and cultural zeal, so that many
ostensibly “objective” analysis in African philosophy are in fact disguised
recommendations of African first-order system. Moses Oke’s explication may
have to be considered here. For him, “it is common for cultures to fade away
and be replaced by new or old ones, and for cultures to vary from society to
society and from age to age” (OKE 2006, 332). But as I would like to
moderately express the point, a support for Moses Oke’s view would not be
misplaced; an African philosopher, I believe, cannot wholly detach the unifying
cultural structure that, as an analytic, methodologist or culturalist, guides his
detailed investigations of African problems, from the unifying structure which,
as an African’s ideal, he thinks ought to prevail in African affairs and hopes
may sometimes be more fully realized. His African theory in philosophy is thus
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
essentially a program of action along two lines which are kept in some measure
of harmony with each other by that African problem—problem in assimilating
African facts for purposes of systematic understanding, and problem in aiming
at progressively molding the distinct African pattern, so far as he (the African
philosopher) can influence it, into what he thinks it ought to be.
It is surely beyond serious dispute that African philosophers do in fact
often import their own culture into their analyses of African phenomena. Moses
Oke’s reason for this is that “the indigenous social culture was superimposed
upon Africa and Africans by alien colonialist cultures leading to a confused
cultural amalgam in which Western conceptions of the good have been imposed
upon African thought and conduct” (2006, 332). The conscious design of
separate cultures and cultural understanding, as implied using Oke’s analysis,
will become a device to express the tendency of maturity in each culture or part
of nature. (It is also undoubtedly true that even thinkers who believe human
condition can be studied with the culture neutrality characterizing every inquiry
into objective activities, and who often pride themselves on the absence of
culture orientation from their own analyses in African philosophy, do in fact
sometimes makes judgments from their own analyses of African condition.
Even if culture predications are assumed to be inherently capable of proof or
disproof by European philosophical tradition, at least some of the differences
between African philosophers involving culture-orientation are not in fact
resolved by the procedures of controlled inquiry.
It does not appear so easy in African philosophy to prevent, in any
event, aversions, hopes and fears from coloring the conclusions that
philosophers will arrive at. It has taken countless years of efforts to develop
habits and techniques of investigation which help safeguard philosophical
dispositions and inquiries in European philosophical traditions against the
intrusion of irrelevant personal factors; and even in this case, the protection
received has not created an infallible or conclusive framework. Thus, the
difficulties it creates for achieving objective analyticity in African philosophy
must be admitted.
Admittedly, steps must be taken to identify a culture bias when it occurs
at the maximum, and to minimize if not to eliminate completely its perturbing
effects. What the second reason is analyzing is that it would be no less absurd to
conclude that reliable knowledge of human affairs is unattainable merely
because inquiry in African philosophy is frequently culture-oriented. What this
means is that relative standards by different investigators are used (ends sought,
standards employed), whereas there are no absolute standards (we only have
evaluation of the end result only in different continents where different
investigators carry out their study).
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
The Approval of Cultural Facts
There is a more sophisticated argument for the view that African philosophy
cannot be culture-free. It maintains that the distinction between fact and culture
assumed in the preceding discussion is untenable when purposive African
culture is being analyzed, since in this context culture enter inextricably into
what appear to be purely factual statements. Accordingly, those who subscribe
to this thesis claim that a culture-neutral African philosophy is in principle
impossible, and not simply that it is difficult to attain. For if value and culture
are indeed so fused that they cannot even be distinguished, cultural judgments
cannot be eliminated from African philosophy, unless all predications are also
eliminated from them, and therefore, unless other philosophies that are not of
Africa completely disappear. In this regard, Messay Kebede’s belief in the
African form of cultural modernity cannot be ignored. He is of the view that,
“the involvement of African philosophical, cultural or traditional discourse
provides the proof that values and spiritual pursuits are most active in making of
African modernity” (2004, 12-13). His view describes one thing; the African
reaction to appearance of objectivity raises questions of the kind compelling us
to upgrade our understanding of development and modernity instead of relying
on conventional answers (KEBEDE 2004, 34). A conventional answer, to a
great extent, is the belief that African philosophy is not culture-free. As African
philosophy is not culture free, it does not mean that it is inferior and it does not
mean that it has to be subdued or become a second-string form of philosophical
or cultural discourse.
For example, it has been argued by Richard H. Bell (1997, 2002), Peter
Bodunrin (1984), and Robin W.G. Horton (1997), that the African philosopher
must distinguish between traditional and undesirable forms of African system,
on failing in his plain duty to present African condition truthfully and faithfully,
the prohibition against culture-judgments in African philosophy would lead to
the consequence that we are permitted to give a strictly factual description of
philosophical issues that can be seen in European philosophy, while Odera
Oruka (1998, 177), Niyi Osundare (1998, 229-230), Bruce Janz (2003, 34-6),
and Kwasi Wiredu (1998, 194-5) assert that we would not be permitted to speak
of the cruelty that has once happened to Africa during colonialism and the
neocolonial effects of Western friendship with Africa on the psyche of Africans.
A political scientist is allowed to see things from his perspective, while a
philosopher historian is permitted to see things from the perspective of
analyticity and do a critique of how imagination can be used to take a look at
historical event. What may be claimed to be a straightforward view in European
philosophy may be different in African philosophy.
Moreover, the assumption implicit in the recommendation discussed
above for achieving culture-neutrality in European philosophy is often rejected
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
as hopelessly naïve, it will be recalled, that relations of means to ends can be
established without commitments to these ends, so that the conclusions of
African philosophical inquiry concerning culture are objective views of life
which make conditional rather than categorical assertions about culture. This is
because, the choice men make between alternative means of obtaining a given
end depends on the cultural view they ascribe to those alternatives.
If there is any proposition made that African philosophy is culture-laden,
it does not entail the conclusion, that, in a manner unique to the study of African
philosophy, value and culture are fused beyond the possibility of distinguishing
between them. It is worthy to note that, the claim that there is such a fusion and
that a culture-free African philosophy is therefore inherently absurd, confounds
two quite different senses of the term “culture judgment”: the sense in which a
culture judgment expresses approval or disapproval either of some religious,
moral or social ideal, or of some cultural view, of or some cultural action (or
cultural institution) because of a commitment to such an ideal; and the sense in
which a culture judgment expresses an estimate of the degree to which some
commonly recognized (and more or less clearly defined) type of cultural action,
object, or institution is embodied in a given stance (See, WIREDU 1998, 307-8;
WIREDU 1998, 193-4).
Furthermore, to make any decision, an investigator, whether an African
or Euro-American, must judge whether the evidence warrants the conclusion set
to be made whether in African philosophy or European philosophical tradition.
Nonetheless, when an investigator reaches a conclusion within the cultural
framework where he is doing his investigation, he can therefore be said to be
making a specific “cultural value-judgment”, in the sense that he has in mind
some standardized type of cultural condition designated, and what he knows and
calls the object in view and that he assesses what he knows about the specimen
with the measure provided by this assumed standard.
On the other hand, the African philosopher may also make a quite
different sort of cultural judgment, which asserts that, since a cultural object
under consideration has diminished powers of remaining under continuous
examination, it is an undesirable condition. An African philosopher with
specific interest in Yoruba thought may be interested in how some events are
tagged cultural and metaphysical at the same time. Take for instance, a person’s
iwa (character) which makes an individual meaningful or meaningless in the
human society, is what makes people to have good memory of the individual
after his demise. Thus, how has the concept of iwa as character become
existential? The response may lie in the notion that the concept of iwa has two
attributes (GBADEGESIN 1998, 303-5): the character aspect where it makes an
individual to relate with other individuals in the moral community and the
existential aspect which creates a good or bad memory and which allows
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
judgment to be passed on the person. Like the African philosopher: (Yoruba
example), a Euro-American philosopher may be interested in characterizing
certain objects in his field of research as philosophical, psychological or natural;
but, also like the African philosopher, he is in addition expressing his cultural
approval or disapproval of the characteristics he is ascribing to his research. The
difficulties that African philosophers with the European counterparts raise
provide no compelling reasons for the claim that a culturally neutral African
philosophy is inherently impossible.
The Approval of Evidence
There remains for consideration the claim that a culture-free European
philosophy is impossible, because culture commitments enter into the very
assessment of evidence by European philosophers, and not simply into the
contents of the conclusions they advance. This is typical of Moses Makinde’s
African Philosophy: The Demise of a Controversy. Similarly, some African
thinkers tend to believe in this form of framework. Precisely, Kwame
Nkrumah’s Consciencism (1998), Julius Nyerere’s Ujamaa: The Basis of
African Socialism (1971), Obafemi Awolowo’s Democratic Socialism (2010,
170-205), Nelson Mandela’s Interventionism in Apartheid (2013), and so forth,
are proponents thereof. Moses Makinde, in his work, African Philosophy: The
Demise of a Controversy, asserts that the analytic school’s view of philosophy is
just one of many views and their conception of the nature and subject matter of
philosophy is personal to members of that school (2010, 23). He says, “African
thought hold positions quite similar to many ancient and recent European
philosophers” (MAKINDE 2010, 28-9). This assertion helps to understand the
notion that culture commitments enter into the very assessment of evidence by
European and African philosophers, and not simply into the contents of the
conclusions they advance. If culture commitments do not enter into the contents
of the conclusions that European philosophers advance, then, the conceptions of
the culture held by an African philosopher of what constitute cogent evidence or
sound intellectual workmanship are the products of his cultural education and
his place in the society, and are affected by the social cultural values transmitted
by his training and associated with his cultural position; accordingly, the
cultural values to which an African philosopher is thereby committed determine
which statements he accepts as well-grounded conclusions about African
cultural affairs. Thus, the differences between African philosophers in respect to
what they accept as credible can sometimes be attributed to the influence of
cultural, religious, and other kinds of bias.
No matter how investigations are conducted in the African and European
ways, the culture-oriented bias of each continent would help where the evidence
will be taken and in situating where the outcome would be placed. Each culture
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
helps in giving reliable instances or knowledge about the world. The problem is
just that these different cultural environments would help research in a lot of
ways; the world will be seen from different angles just like an elephant will be
viewed from different angles. Inquiries are not meant to be conducted in the
same way using the same methodology. African cultural life differs from the
European lifestyle, in the sense that, if childless marriages are to be examined
using the European condition and the African condition, different results will be
arrived at because their societies and belief-system strictly differs. A relational
form of objectivity between African perception of a childless marriage and the
Euro-American perception of a childless marriage, which is called relationism,
to a great extent, cannot be achieved (see, JANZ 2003, 36-7). In any way that
we may want to analyze the issue at hand, it suffices to say that the cultural
conclusion that an African philosopher would reach is marked by ‘objectivity’
because of the peculiarity of his cultural environment, where the same is
applicable to the European investigator under the European cultural condition.
In brief, the various reasons we have been examining for the endemic
impossibility of securing objectivity where each culture has its own standard of
objectifying issues do not establish what many European philosophers purport
to establish, even though in some instances, an European philosopher or trained
professional African philosophers direct attention to undoubtedly important
practical difficulties frequently encountered in the African cultural discourse.
However, Peter Kanyandago differs from this conclusion. The trend of
westernization of Africa, he says, “has become very pervasive,” because
inculturation implies a re-appropriation of cultures (KANYANDAGO 2003, 32
33). Because of the western dominated African life or re-appropriation of
African culture, he rejected the African form of humanity. This, to a great
extent, cast doubt on any form of objectivity which could have been reached by
the African cultural inquirers and environment. However, there is a response
from William Emmanuel Abraham to Kanyandago’s doubt. In trying to show
that each culture has different understanding concerning the nature of man
coupled with his ability to conduct cultural inquiry, he (William Abraham)
pointed out that “if possession of reason is part of our nature (or, if reasoning is
part of the description of how people conduct their affairs or cultural
investigation in different cultures), then, we cannot be enslaved by reason”
(ABRAHAM 1966, 80-1), hence, reason is unworthy to create cultural
inferiority. What William Abraham purport to establish is that; reason is
possible in different cultures, because man cannot be enslaved to reason so as to
be led to casting doubt on what are the end-products of what ‘others’ carry out.
William Abraham’s view, to a great extent, reflects the claim of this study.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
The Grounds for the Objective-Status of African Philosophy
For as much as this study has examined some of the grounds that have been put
forward for the contention that African philosophy is culture-prejudiced, it was
quite easy to distinguish the four groups of such reasons, such that the
discussion, thus far, has helped in dealing in turn with the asserted role of
culture in the choice of problems, the determination of the contents of
conclusions, the acceptance of cultural facts, and the appraisal of evidence
between what the African and European investigators do.
Emevwo Biakolo in the Categories of Cross-cultural Cognition and the
African Condition, asserts that, it is in consonance with the pattern of growth
and development of the new science of anthropology which replaced the old
science of subject-object relations that the determining factor becomes the issue
of race (1998, 1). Race is used based on the particularity of Africa as distinct
from Europe. Thus, the issue of objectivity, as Biakolo has helped us to
discover, paves the way for the factors that makes African investigator to be
easily distinguished from the European counterpart when it comes to whatever
is chosen to be investigated. If we assert that there is no cultural difference, or
that races do not exist (as Kwame Appiah asserts in his works of 1992, 1996,
2005 and 2006), then, we need to heed Emevwo Biakolo’s warning that “an
ingenuity will be revealed which will help us to further confirm that there is a
political project behind the western construction of the cultural paradigms of the
“Other” (1998, 1). If Biakolo’s paradigm (which Bruce Janz (2003, 34-38)
further reiterates) stands, it will be consistent with the notion that African
culture, African philosophy or black race has no objective standing in the
universe. But if Biakolo’s ingenuity (which is a rejection of Appiah’s assertion)
is followed, it will presuppose the notion that there is no fundamental difference
between what African investigators investigate and what European investigators
try to investigate.
We may want to consider it not quite necessary to follow the line of the
argument that has been put forward. The nature of this unnecessariness may
arise from a critic’s view as predicated upon Kwame Appiah’s assertion that
there are no races: there is nothing in the world that can do all we ask race to
do for us (1992, 45). Be it as it may, the implication that his claim creates is that
there is no need of classifying people into few races because classifying books
in the library would not help us in reflecting or knowing the deep facts about
books (APPIAH 1992, 38). For as much as this claim may help in advancing the
idea of globality, it can be used in boxing Appiah to a corner. He fails to
acknowledge the mental ascription of culture; where people are so biased about
who they are, where they come from, the values they represent, what they need
to say or withhold, and how they must communicate. There is still a whole lot to
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
say about different but not opposing cultures and about what makes Africa
distinct as Africa and not what makes Africa become a collegiate with Europe.
In his work, Old Gods, New Worlds, Kwame Appiah claims that for the
African intellectual, of course, the problem is whether – and, if so, how – our
(African) cultures are to become modern. He concludes by saying that, neither
of us (Africa and Europe) will understand what modernity is until we
understand each other (1992, 107). It is somewhat obvious that despite his
(Appiah’s) initial claim that there are no races, he asserts in another work that
Africa and Europe needs to understand each other. What will be the nature and
scope of this understanding? Entering into Appiah’s mind using his earlier
work, The Illusions of Race would presuppose a confusing analogy. There are
no races, he (Appiah) said, and now, Africa and Europe need to understand each
other, is a presupposition of (i) confusion, and (ii) that races exist. In conclusion,
it means an African investigator differs from his/her European counterpart, that
Africa differs from Europe, and that any European anthropologist cannot
conclusively understand why Africans choose to carry out a particular thing in
their culture. For example, a European investigator or anthropologist cannot
understand why Africans (e.g., some parts of the Yoruba people) choose to erect
two effigies to represent twins (ère ìbejì) and decide to give the cultural or
lineage panegyrics of these effigies. To arrive at a conclusion that such practice
is pre-logical is to be preposterous. Janheinz Jahn observes in Muntu: African
Culture and the Western World that “all activities of men, and the movements in
nature, rest on the word, on the productive power of the word, which is water
and heat and seed and Nommo, that is, life force itself …. The force,
responsibility, and commitment of the word, and the awareness that the word
alone alters the world …. In traditional African culture, a new born child is a
mere thing until his father gives and speak his name” (1961, 128). It is now
commonly known that to speak of other cultural understanding about a
particular thing as preposterous because of pre-logicality, is to be mistaken.
Janheinz Jahn’s opinion, in this respect, is that “the African tradition as it
appears in the light of neo-colonial culture may be a legend – but it is the legend
in which African intelligence believes” (1961, 19). This presupposes one thing
that this study affirms; the African cultural understanding and analysis of a
specific thing is neither preposterous, religious, savagery, archaic, inferior, brute
nor pre-logical. The idea that the African cultural understanding or analysis of a
thing or situation should be found or done within the limit of the cosmopolitan
or global world view is an attempt to encourage reductio ad absurdum. But, this
is Pecksniffian in nature. Janheinz Jahn’s assertion is that the position of the
West, which sees African culture as being doomed to destruction or
homogenization, is mistaken. African culture, as Janheinz Jahn posit, is
evolving into a rich and independent civilization that is capable of incorporating
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
those elements of the West that do not threaten its basic values. Though Julius
Nyerere’s in Ujamaa: The Basis of African Socialism (1971, 91-95) lend
support to Jahn Janheinz’s position by asserting that it is the attitude of the mind
to help one another in the communal African society and to help develop the
African socio-cultural values that best describe the African condition, however,
the problem with Nyerere’s Ujamaa is that it is a caricature of Scientific
Socialism (Marxism), which proposes that socialism must come through
proletarian revolution within an already developed capitalist state.
In this regard, the distinctiveness of the culture and cultural
understanding of the African condition as exhibited and explicated by Kwame
Anthony Appiah in Old Gods, New Worlds (1998, 245-74), B. Du Bois in The
Conservation of Races (1998, 269-74), Richard H. Bell's Understanding African
Philosophy: A Cross-Cultural Approach to Classical and Contemporary Issues
(2002, 197-220), Robin William G. Horton's Patterns of Thought in Africa and
the West: Essays on Magic, Religion and Science (1997), etc., help in asserting
the objective status of what African investigators do with cultural facts as
different from what European investigators do with the tools of philosophical
analysis.
In African, African American, Africana Philosophy, Lucius Outlaw
opines that “philosophizing is inherently grounded in socially shared practices,
not in transcendental rules. When we view philosophical practices historically,
sociologically, and comparatively, we are led inescapably to conclude that
philosophical practice is inherently pluralistic, and all philosophical ideals are
local to communities of thinkers. Since African peoples are ethnically – hence
culturally – diverse and geographically dispersed, very important aspects of
these ethnic and geographical diversities were fueled, in significant part, by the
incursions of Europeans and others into Africa” (1998, 29). If Lucius Outlaw’s
framework is encouraged, then, the ground for separate investigations between
African investigators and their European or American counterparts would not be
seen as prejudices but distinct fields of inquiry.
There may be other ways of analyzing Appiah’s view that there are no
races and DuBois’ counter-claim that individual races are to be conserved
because they have distinct messages to deliver to the world. However, Emevwo
Biakolo’s view that it is the Western political project that actually distinguishes
the world of the “Other”, and Leopold Senghor’s claim that “Negroid
civilization had flourished in the Upper Palaeolithic Age, where the Neolithic
Revolution could not be explained without them” (1998, 439), are clear
representations of distinct viewpoints which we must recognize as not
conflicting. These views, Leopold Senghor maintains that, they “set us on the
way to racialism” (1998, 439). Similarly, Tsenay Serequeberhan’s view that
“the closing years of the twentieth century are bound to be for Africa and
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
Africans for a time of prolonged, deep reflection and self-examination” (1998,
9), Kwame Nkrumah’s suggestion of a cultural revivalist solution that will
revive the African cultural values of the past into the present (1974, 79), and
Henry Olela’s position that “the authentic theoretical foundation of African
diaspora’s experience is African” (1998, 43), serve as, (i) counter-objection to
Kwame Appiah’s claim in the Illusions of Race (1992), and as explicated in his
recent work, Color Conscious: The Political Morality of Race (1996), where he
defended the view that the concept of race is a mistaken American idea
(APPIAH and GUTMAN 1996, 32); The Ethics of Identity (2005), where he
defended
the
term
‘collective
identity’(APPIAH
2005,
21-22);
Cosmopolitanism: Ethics in a World of Strangers (2006), and (ii) a major boost
to aid the notions that there is distinctive Africanness in the way African
philosophy has chosen to divulge itself, and that, there is the objectivity that is
peculiar to African philosophical inquiry or investigation.
Conclusion
This study does not represent an attempt to split philosophical or cultural
investigation among different cultures, as it does not also aim to conclude that
cultural investigation is universal in nature and scope. What it aims to produce
is a sort of relativism which would not damage the essentialist discourse of
putting universal attributes behind human acts, behaviours and plans. Diogenes
Laertius’s claim as espoused by Appiah that “he (Diogenes) is a citizen of the
world” has long been laid to rest. The shortcomings that World War I could not
address gave birth to World War II; Al Qaeda dominates the East of the globe
based on what the perpetrators deem as religious and political marginalization;
colonialism took place in Africa and the socio-political and economic effects are
still on-going in the lives of the Africans and in the activities of the African
countries, and so on, as we can count. The conclusion of this study that there is
distinctive Africanness in the way African philosophy has chosen to divulge
itself, and that, there is the objectivity that is peculiar to African philosophical
inquiry cannot walk hand-in-hand with Appiah’s fear, which is that relativism
gave birth to the separation between values and facts and this could spell doom
for cosmopolitanism and its core values. However, it is important we note that
no matter what Kwame Appiah may concede in his works, what an African
investigator chooses to investigate, will always be consistent with his cultural
world-view. This is because each specific human race or continents have their
beliefs which have guided their relationship with ‘others’. However, this study
concedes that what a European investigator chooses to investigate will be
consistent with his understanding of the world around him just like an African
investigator who inquires about the culture or world around him.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
Relevant Literature
1. ABRAHAM, William. [The Mind of Africa], 1966. University of Chicago
Press: Illinois, Chicago. Paperback.
2. APPIAH, Kwame. [Cosmopolitanism: Ethics in a World of Strangers],
2006. W.W. Norton & Company: New York. Paperback.
3. -----
.“Old Gods, New Worlds,” [In My Father’s House: African
Philosophy in the Philosophy of Culture], pp107-136, 1992. Oxford
University Press: Oxford. Paperback.
4. -----
. [The Ethics of Identity], 2005. Princeton University Press:
Princeton. Paperback.
5. -----
.“The Illusions of Race,” [In My Father’s House: African Philosophy
in the Philosophy of
Culture],
Oxford University Press: Oxford. Paperback.
6.
pp28-46,
1992.
GUTMAN, A. [Color Conscious: The Political Morality of Race],
1996. Princeton University Press: Princeton. Paperback.
7. BELL, Richard. [Understanding African Philosophy: A Cross-Cultural
Approach to Classical and
Contemporary
Routledge: London. Paperback.
Issues],
2002.
8. BIAKOLO, Emevwo. “Categories of Cross-Cultural Cognition and the
African Condition,” [The African Philosophy Reader, PIETER, Coetzee
and ABRAHAM, Roux Eds.], pp1-14, 1998. Routledge: London.
Paperback.
9. BODUNRIN, Peter. “The Question of African Philosophy,” [African
Philosophy: An Introduction,
Richard, WRIGHT Ed., 3rd
edn.), pp1-24, 1984. University Press of America: Lanham. Paperback.
10. DU BOIS, William Edward. “The Conservation of Races,” [African
Philosophy: An Anthology,
Chukwudi, EZE Ed.),
pp269-274, 1998. Blackwell Publishers: Oxford. Paperback.
11. EZEUGWU, John. “Ethnocentric Bias in African Philosophy vis-à-vis
Asouzu’s Ibuanyidanda Ontology,” [Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of
African Philosophy, Culture and Religions],
pp41-49, Jan-Jun, 2014.
Vol 3. No 1. Paperback.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
12. GBADEGESIN, Segun. “Individuality, Community, and the Moral Order,”
[The African Philosophy Reader, PIETER, Coetzee and ABRAHAM,
Roux, Eds.], pp292-305, 1998. Routledge: London. Paperback.
13. HALLEN, Barry. [A Short History of African Philosophy], 2002. Indiana
University Press: Bloomington, IN. Paperback.
14. HORTON, Robin. [Patterns of Thought in Africa and the West: Essays on
Magic, Religion and Science],
1997. Cambridge University
Press: Cambridge, MA. Paperback.
15. JAHN, Janheinz. [Muntu: African Culture and the Western World], 1961.
The Groove Press: Chicago. Paperback.
16. JANZ, Bruce. “Between the Particular and the Universal: Cultural Inquiry
as the Encounter between
Anthropology and Philosophy,” [Polylog:
Forum for Intercultural Philosophy], pp30-37, 2003. Vol 4. Web.
17. KANYANDAGO, Peter. “Rejection of the African Humanity: Search for
Cultural Re-Appropriation,”
[African Spirit and
Black Nationalism: A Discourse in African American Studies,
ZENEBU, Falaiye Ed.], pp30-50, 2003. Foresight Press: Lagos. Paperback.
18. KAPHAGAWANI, Didier. “What is African Philosophy?”, [The African
Philosophy Reader, PIETER, Coetzee and ABRAHAM, Roux, Eds.],
pp86-98, 1998. Routledge: London. Paperback.
19. KEBEDE, Messay. “The Future as Forward Movement into the Past: The
Constructedness of Identity,”
[Africa’s
Quest
for
Philosophy of Decolonization], pp12-18, 2004. Vol 42. No 5. Rodopi:
New York. Paperback.
a
20. MAKINDE, Moses. [African Philosophy: The Demise of a Controversy],
2010. Obafemi Awolowo
University Press: Ile-Ife. Paperback.
21. MANGENA, Fainos. “In Defence of Ethnophilosophy: A Brief Response
to Kanu’s Eclecticism,”
[Filosofica Theoretica: Journal of African
Philosophy, Culture and Religions], pp96-107, Jan-Jun, 2014. Vol 3. No 1.
Paperback.
22. MASOLO, Dismas. “African Philosophy and the Postcolonial: Some
Misleading Abstractions about
Identity,”
[Postcolonial
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
African Philosophy: A Critical Reader, Chukwudi, EZE Ed.),
300, 1997. Blackwell Publisher Inc: Cambridge, MA. Paperback.
pp283
23. NAGEL, Ernest. “The Value-Oriented Bias of Social Inquiry,” [Readings
in the Philosophy of Social
Sciences,
Martin,
BRODBECK Ed.), pp98-113, 1968. Macmillan Publishing Co. Inc: New
York. Paperback.
24. NKRUMAH, Kwame. [Consciencism], 1974. Panaf: London. Paperback.
25. NYERERE, Julius. [Ujamaa – The Basis of Socialism], 1971. Oxford
University Press: Oxford. Paperback.
26. OKE, Moses. “Cultural Nostalgia: A Philosophical Critique of Appeals to
the Past in Theories of Re-
Making Africa,” [Nordic Journal
of African Studies], pp332-343, 2006. Vol 15. No 3. Paperback.
27. OLELA, Henry. “The African Foundations of Greek Philosophy,” [African
Philosophy: An Anthology,
Chukwudi, EZE Ed.], pp43-49,
1998. Blackwell Publishers: Oxford, CA. Paperback.
28. ORUKA, Odera. “Sagacity in African Philosophy,” [Readings in African
Philosophy, Sophie, OLUWOLE Ed.], 1991. Mass-tech Publishers: Lagos.
Paperback.
29. OSUNDARE, Niyi. “Squaring Up to Africa’s Future: A Writer’s
Reflection on the Predicament of a
Continent,”
[Remaking
Africa: Challenges of the Twenty-First Century, Olusegun, OLADIPO
Ed.], 1998. Hope Publications: Ibadan. Paperback.
30. OUTLAW, Lucius. “African, African American, Africana Philosophy,”
[African Philosophy: An
Anthology, Chukwudi, EZE
Ed.], pp23-42, 1998. Blackwell Publishers: Oxford. Paperback.
31. SENGHOR, Leopold. “Negritude and African Socialism,” [The African
Philosophy Reader, PIETER,Coetzee and ABRAHAM, Roux Eds.],
pp438-448, 1998. Routledge: London. Paperback.
32. SEREQUEBERHAN, Tsenay. “Philosophy and the Post-Colonial Africa,”
[African Philosophy: An
Anthology,
Chukwudi,
EZE Ed.), pp9-22, 1998. Blackwell Publishers: Oxford. Paperback.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
33. WIREDU, Kwasi. “How Not to Compare African Thought with Western
Thought,” [African Philosophy:
An Anthology, Chukwudi, EZE Ed.),
pp193-199, 1998. Blackwell Publishers: Oxford. Paperback.
Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and Religions
SCIENTIFIC PROGRESS AND POSTMODERN CULTURE: THE
AFRICAN EXPERIENCE
Isaiah NEGEDU, PhD
Department of Philosophy,
Federal University Lafia, Nasarawa State
Abstract
Scientific discourse grew out of various philosophical puzzles raised by human
beings from the period of antiquity; and each age always comes with a renewed
vigor for development over previous schools of thought with their attendant
theories. With the speed of scientific progress and scientific awareness, there is
no doubt that scholars from various disciplines fashion out theories to meet with
the demands of the scientific spirit. It is this very presence of the scientific
society that leads to contest for relevance among various theories/schools of
thought. The African situation has been quite unique as the development of
science is greeted with the idea that scientific developments have moral
boundaries. Critically looking at development in science and how it has tailored
our outlook in contemporary times, we opine that scientific investigations into
phenomena make philosophical debates more relevant in our modern world.
Keywords: Science, Scientific Progress, Post Modernity, Dialectic, Culture,
African Experience.
Introduction
The main characteristic that preoccupies every debate both in the realm of
scholarship and informal discourse has been the place of man in the universe and
how to solve the problems of the human person. Thus, humanism has been a
prevalent theme associated with the second half of the 20th century down through
the 21st century. The tone of the criticism leveled against scholarship during the
classical times gives an insight into the escapist attitude of philosophers from the
social strife of man, which was preoccupied by a journey into changeless reality.
Though the existence of science dates back almost immediately to the classical
age, there was less freedom of thought that enables man to explore various
possibilities. The reason for this attitude was either because it would change the
course of history physically, or the fear that people will be induced to change
their mental orientation into various belief systems. Science did not to exist to
serve as a threat to various schools of thought but to search for meeting points of
disciplines that gives more worth to the human person.
Classical philosophy largely favors the African system with its emphasis
on the preservation of tradition; hence the slow pace of radical scientific
movements. But even post-modern thinking is quite impressive in the sense that
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
it was not built in isolation, at least, there was a foundation and such foundations
made it necessary to see the errors inherent in classical thought. Why should
discourse on the freedom of thought be necessary, but for the fact that there was
an intention to subsume the freedom of man into a system. It is with this same
spirit of appreciation of post-modern thought through the lens of classical
thinking, that scientific progress in Africa should be seen through the lens of
African tradition.
Evolution of Scientific Progress
The etymological meaning of science suggests that it is a peculiar form of
knowledge with wide applications. One of the characteristics of science therefore
is its ability to embrace other disciplines other than the experimental sciences. As
a form of knowledge, its application in classical antiquity was primarily within
the domain of philosophy. Thus, scientific development without recourse to its
root would amount to sterile scholarship. It is in this regard that every form of
scientific discipline, particularly of the experimental sciences employs the
critical-analytic method to arrive at solutions to problems. However, the
distinctive mark between the former applications of science from the post
modern age was the limiting of science when there is perceived threat to the
meta-empirical world. The reason science is considered as a reactionary
discipline is not necessarily because it denies the existence of the supernatural
realm, but its insistence on the negligence of that realm and total focus on the
natural world if man is going to encounter progress from one generation to
another. This appears to be an extreme borne out of the hate of metaphysics. The
implications of this view is even more for the experimental sciences than for any
other discipline because the tentativeness of solutions in scientific advancement
is more pronounced that it has become a feature of science.
This has rightly influenced the history of science to be the replacement of
false theories by theories that are considered to be true. Scientific revolutions at
the dawn of the modern period were fundamental to the extent that scholarship
before the 15th century was seen to be pre-scientific. By and large, the various
revolutions in science has shown that progress in science could be gradual and
incremental or radically discontinuous. The various theories of evolution of
scientific theories fall within these two categories. Those who uphold the notion
of scientific advancement as radically discontinuous opine that past theories that
are not workable for the current age should be absolutely detached from current
scientific notions of progress that produce tentative results. Scientific progress,
advancement, development or whatever its appellation may be, is only possible
because there is always an existing structure on ground that is unfavorable for
scholarship. As a result of the self-critical attitude of science therefore, theories
are replaced with old ones. According to Larry Laudan:
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
…it is vividly clear that the views of the scientific community about
how to test theories and about what counts as evidence have changed
dramatically through history… The fact that the evaluative strategies of
scientists of earlier eras are different from our strategies makes it
quixotic to suppose that we can access the rationality of their science
by ignoring completely their views about how theories should be
evaluated. (1996, 80)
An insistence on the history of scientific progress without reference to flawed
theories that gave birth to current theories is a contradiction in terms because
gradual progressiveness necessarily implies the presence of existing structures.
That is why John Losee opines that “a progressive sequence is constituted by
stages each of which is superior to its predecessor” (2004, 7). Thus, scientific
advancement cannot be associated only with descriptive progress.
Descriptiveness alone does not produce the self critical attitude needed in
science; hence the relevance of theoretical progress. That is why theories must be
fashioned to determine how man could better live in the world.
It is this very notion of uncertainty that makes scientific investigations
unending. Karl Popper succinctly noted it when he said: “The game of science is,
in principle, without end. He who decides one day that scientific statements do
not call for any further test and that they can be regarded as finally verified,
retires from the game” (1992, 32). Pyotr Fedoseyev aptly stated that our age is
primarily concerned with the importance of philosophy of science towards
analyzing the role of scientific and technical progress in the life of man and
society in general. Knowledge in general has always returned to man, so that on
the final analysis, even the science of metaphysics which has undergone several
negative criticisms is studied in order to teach man how to live in the world
(1989, 3). Natural scientists have always considered the solutions of the problems
of man to be the primary aim of science. Thus, scientific progressiveness is more
often characterized by its ability to set goals and to a large extent make those
goals achievable. The result of science has a more radically immanent application
“… the aim of science is to secure theories with a high problem-solving
effectiveness” (LAUDAN 1996, 77). The dividends of this goal of science are
worth-noting; it takes into account scientific progress as it was in the past in line
with its futuristic value. It also assures goals that have immanent bearing thereby
bringing it closer to epistemic access (LAUDAN 1996, 78).
The Logic of Science
Science has its own progressive tool of reasoning. Historical developments in
scholarship show that it uses a method of analysis and synthesis to arrive at its
results. The validation of scientific inquiry lies primarily within its logic. That is
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
why the scientist is that scholar who is always guided by the accepted rules of
logical reasoning. To be competent as a scientist therefore, one should be
competent in logical reasoning; it is a methodical reasoning that the scientific
method should employ. When viewed holistically, the logic of science takes the
Hegelian dialectical pattern of a thesis-antithesis-synthesis. It is a continuous
process, though not routinely applied because of its accommodation of
alternative possibilities. What guarantees alternative possibilities is the very fact
of the theory of probability that sustains science.
Probability as a theory does not guarantee outright certainty, but its
nearness to precision and or truth is highly probable than doubt. But the method
of science is not completely inferential in its probable form; no matter how
plausible our reasoning process may be, in the midst of various analogies, we
creatively employ deductive reasoning. Whether plausible reasoning is limited to
laboratory experimentation is another issue for determination. However, even the
untrained mind through creative reasoning uses logic in commonsensical
experiences. Scientific knowledge combines both the principles of experimental
and theoretical reasoning to arrive at a method that takes all disciplines into
cognizance. The scientific society cannot therefore be devoid of method.
Methodology in this regard deals with the principles of the organization of
knowledge and each science has special demands on organization.
Post Modernity
Post modernity is generally associated with an economic, cultural or scientific
condition of society which comes almost immediately after modernity. From the
philosophical perspective, post modernity marks the end of modernity. When
viewed from the angle of any discipline, it represents a gradual movement that
comes to play through some form of creative dialectic and it is marked by
continuity. It emerged as a response to some perceived problems posed by
modernity.
Philosophers from the period of antiquity viewed nature from a unitary
perspective that was supernal in its own right. The human person and all meta
empirical forces were regarded as part of nature thereby setting the rules of
conduct for man. Its implication for the society at such moment was that reason
was determined or curtailed by nature; the human person and all suprasensible
beings were made for nature and not the other way round. Man in this sense was
not free to explicate nature wholly for its exploitation. The Judeo-Christian
conception of God gradually eroded the concept of logos as proffered by the
classical scholars. It would not have been possible for the creator of the world to
be fully involved with nature in human terms. This pantheistic view of God was
replaced with the monotheistic concept. By embracing God, humans could attain
universal truth. This Thomistic view of world order was a defining moment for
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
science as it raised relevant questions and objections. These objections were due
in part to the fact that empirical investigations into the natural world order had
some results that were contrary to certain divine revelations. The most prominent
was the Copernican revolution by Nicholas Copernicus: “…which held that the
earth moved around the sun in contradiction to several passages in the scriptures
that referred to the earth as unmoving” (PARFITT 2002, 14). Prior to
Copernicus’ scientific investigations, Ockham had earlier denied that human
beings could have access to God’s universal truths through scientific
experimentation: “…since God was all-powerful he was not limited by human
rationality or by nature, which were merely particular creations among the
infinity of creativity of which God was capable” (PARFITT 2002, 14). This
therefore puts the foundation of human knowledge into question. The emergence
of modern science paved way for the molding of nature in accord with human
needs. Decrease in proximity of divine cause or element meant a conscious
awareness and nearness of people in the ability of science to improve the
wellbeing of man.
Another important element in the emergence of modernity was the
change in the perception that man was entirely part of nature; it gave way for the
concept of the autonomy of the free individual. The human person was not
engulfed in nature in a communal stat to the extent of losing his individuality.
However, modernity still had some deficiencies that slowed its growth toward
science; it was replete with the legitimizing of science in the direction of
conformed dialectic that bothered itself with a meta-discourse. Thus, post
modernity is largely: “…a reaction against these central elements of modernity,
particularly metatheory, foundationalism and subject-object relations…wherein
the subject is allocated an all-powerful position in relation to the object”
(PARFITT 2002, 21).
Evolutionary biology with Darwin as its major proponent greatly
influenced this shift from modern to post modern outlook of the world. The
influence of biology changed the whole concept of life. It postulates that
wherever there is life, there is also activity, there is action. For life to persist,
these activities and behavior that are part of life should be constantly adjusted to
suit the environment. There ceases to be blind conformity to existential realities.
There is room for debates and dialogue that keeps life moving progressively.
Darwin therefore formulated a version of evolution that undergoes modification
through variation and natural selection. It laid the foundation which a naturalistic
approach to the theory of knowledge should take. The insistence on naturalistic
approach to things was not an express denial of any supernatural influence on the
world, but a reaction against speculated questions without attempt to relate such
issues to observational evidence (LEWENS 2007, 191). In line with this theory,
scientific progress was viewed from the evolutionary perspective “…within
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
which natural selection operates on a set of conceptual variants such that the
fittest variants survive” (LOSEE 2004, 141).
Lyotard who is credited with the emergence of the idea of post
modernism opines that knowledge does not legitimizes itself without room for
academic debates that justifies its proof (BENHABIB 1984, 119). He sees the
concept of post-modernity as very critical in the development of the world and
scientific progress. Thus accordingly, Jean-Francois Lyotard opined: “post
modernism refines our sensitivity to differences and reinforces our ability to
tolerate the incommensurable. Its principle is not the expert’s homology, but the
inventor’s paralogy” (1984, xxv). By this, post modernism encourages a
knowledge-based approach that is radically discontinuous from classical
knowledge that has its foundation on meta-narratives. But meta-narratives are not
altogether unscientific, since classical thought is not entirely devoid of the
inventor’s paralogy, though to some extent, it was detached from practical human
condition.
Toward a Synthetic Analysis
The dialectics of post modern culture always moves in the direction of scientific
development. Most times, we tend to think that science precedes post modernity
in terms of technological progress. While the notion of scientific development is
incontestable, attitude of various disciplines towards such movement is an
entirely unique issue. The gradual unfolding of post modern thought necessarily
entails that its primary aim is to ensure that it goes in line with the scientific
spirit. It means that in all facets of development notwithstanding the discourse
involved, there should not be a dialectical reversal into traditionalism. Historical
development has shown that to some extent, science has enjoyed an unguarded
freedom, which has led to placement of less value on the moral worth of
scientific research. This brings into question the supposed intention of science to
take the human person into consideration in its development. If reactions to
classical and modern thoughts by post modernity were because scholarship in
former times took an escapist route from the existential conditions of man, then
scholarship in current times should be primarily concerned with the enhancement
of the dignity of man. But history has shown that their development proceeds in
quite a contradictory way; quite often, they have not discovered the truth so much
as distorted and concealed it “…the achievements of the natural sciences were to
a great extent used against humanity, particularly in the destructive wars of the
20th century” (FEDOSEYEV 1989, 4). It is this very problem of the moral worth
of scientific progress that takes the ontological dimension that bothers on
philosophy. What makes various disciplines including science scientific is not
because of the provision of experimental data for observation in the laboratory,
but because of that critical analytic attitude that philosophy provides. Some of the
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
problems inherent in science is because of the refusal of science to take some of
its issues to the philosophical level. The interaction of philosophy as a world
outlook and as a method of scientific knowledge can only progress when the
dogmatism inherent in each discipline is loosened. “…the manifestations of
dogmatism and authoritarianism are still felt to this day. This is why the
philosophical comprehension of the changes taking place in modern natural
science should become a school for a new, dialectical creative thinking”
(FEDOSEYEV 1989, 9).
For science to meet the needs of man in the society it has to be used as a
force of socio-cultural engineering otherwise scientism which sees science as the
beginning and end of all that exists in the universe is deified. Though scientific
knowledge strictly speaking is capable of solving most of human problems, the
deification of science has been antithetical to human progress. Uncontrolled
scientific progress has more implications even for science than for any other
discipline. This is because the very chain of thought which scientism intends to
discard carries with it some of the logical foundations of scientific knowledge.
On the other hand, antiscientism which is an outright rejection of science also
tends towards negation of human progress. We cannot trust the future of the
world into some supernal principles without regard for naturalism. There is a
meeting point between scientism and antiscientism, and it is to the effect that
both schools of thought negate scientific knowledge for the benefit of man. Any
attempt to enthrone either naturalism or supernaturalism is injurious as it places
little value on human existence. While scientism has been responsible for the
destruction of lives and properties through the invention of atomic bombs which
have been used in various world wars and civil unrest in different societies,
antiscientism has been used in different historical periods by various religious
sects to enthrone the suprasensible world through a God-centered religion that
sees the world as a divine arrangement thereby destroying all forces that are
perceived to oppose such arrangement. Ironically, both schools of thought are
one-directional in their thinking leaving no room for alternative possibilities. Any
appeal to enchantment or disenchantment in its negative form that leads to
antiscientism or scientism as the case may be, is a total disconnect from the goal
and end of science. Such ideologies are nothing but a complete replication of
Popper’s closed society and it defies human freedom.
We must aptly note that some parts of Africa are very slow in keying into
the vision of scientific progress. In Nigeria for instance, there has been decrease
in government investment in scientific research over the years, which gradually
demeans the communal status of inquiry and scientific research. Its implication
for the society is that research is largely an affair of the individual. Scientific
research by its nature must be social, lest it ceases to be scientific. You cannot
insist indirectly that education (research) is a private business and expect a social
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
or communal outcome. Notwithstanding the errors that may be inherent in post
modernity, its relevance is seen in its forward movement into the future, the fact
that we can only think of progress that is made possible through a critical
dialectic of change.
Conclusion
It is clear from our analysis that we cannot speak of the separation of scientific
society and postmodern culture. These two concepts move in a progressive
direction through systematic dialectic; hence they become mutually inclusive.
Culture is inherently dynamic and this brings to question the static nature of
African tradition, since to have a culture is to embrace change. Postmodernism
on its own is a culture since it insists on critical reflections on previous schools of
thought. It would be a reversal to demand that post-modern culture should catch
up with the static nature of African tradition. A primary element that is needed to
increase the credibility of our thought system is to embrace the element of self
criticism that steps up the debate from a primitive level to an objective state. In
this sense, even values could be subject to debate so as to arrive to a more
holistic approach to life situations and not merely subjecting it to the relativeness
of ethics, where every society has its own definition of concepts without a point
of compromise.
Relevant Literature
1. BENHABIB, Seyla. “Epistemologies of Postmodernism: A Rejoinder”,
[New German Critique], pp103-126., 1984. No 33. Accessed November
29, 2014. Web.
2. ETIEYIBO, Edwin. “Post-Modern Thinking and African Philosophy”,
[Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and
Religions], pp67-82. Vol 3. No 1. 2014. Paperback.
3. FEDOSEYEV, Pyotr. “Philosophy, Science and Man”, [Studies in Logic
and the Foundations of Mathematics, Barwise, J. et al, Eds.,], pp3-25,
1989. Vol 126. Elsevier Science Publishers: Amsterdam, 3- Paperback.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
4. LAUDAN, Larry. [Beyond Positivism and Relativism], 1996. Westview
Press Inc: Colorado. Paperback.
5. LEWENS, Tim. [Darwin], 2007. Routledge: London. Paperback.
6. LOSEE, John. [Theories of Scientific Progress. An Introduction], 2004.
Routledge: London. Paperback.
7. LYOTARD, J. F. [The Postmodern Condition], 1984. University of
Minnesota: Minneapolis. Paperback.
8. PARFITT, Trevor. [The End of Development? Modernity, Post
Modernity and Development], 2002. Pluto Press: London. Paperback.
9. POPPER, Karl. [The Logic of Scientific Discovery], 1992. Routledge:
London. Paperback.
Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and Religions
UDUDO REASONING IN AFRICAN THOUGHT: A POSTMODERN
FORMALIST METHOD FOR LOGIC
Jonathan O. CHIMAKONAM PhD
Department of Philosophy
University of Calabar
Abstract
The dominance of methods of mathematical reasoning such as the axiomatic
method in modern logic has taken a toll on the independent development of logic
as a separate discipline. However, the emergence of other non-standard systems
of logic which could be described as postmodernist shows how a radical break
might be necessary in salvaging logic from the grip of mathematics. Our goal in
this essay would be to propose and articulate a post modern formalist method
called Ududo Reasoning for logic.
Keywords: Postmodernism, Logic, Ududo, Reasoning, Method, Formalist
Introduction
When every individual thinks in a different way or groups and individuals fail to
understand the thinking of other groups or individuals, then there is a big
problem. Logic is the algorithm of thought and post modernism is a bold and
recalcitrant demonstration that every group if not every individual has his own
model. Underlying the relationships between men or groups is the principle of
intelligibility that makes for understanding of one another’s words,
communications, gesticulations, mannerisms, signals, etc. This principle of
intelligibility is nothing but logic. That individuals or groups understand
themselves is because they belong to the same logic community or that each side
fairly understands the logic of the other side. Where this is not the case, there are
bound to be disagreement, misunderstanding, misreading, misinterpretation,
rancor, crises, trouble, enmity and bitterness. Let us not preclude the regular
possibility of individuals or groups pretending not to understand a logic they
actually understand and thereby causing some of these dangerous situations listed
above just for some selfish reasons. In such cases, it is always easy to know that
there are no genuine cases for misunderstanding or not understanding at all the
logic of communication. And to such individuals or groups, we always reprimand
for their treachery and mischief.
Postmodernism seeks to radicalized everything (OZUMBA &
CHIMAKONAM 2012, 94) with reductions that cut across group-based
relativism to extreme cases of individual relativism. Cases can be made for
individual-based reductions as we see in post modern attitudes to moral
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
standards, but in logic, for once, the limitation of postmodernism is made bare.
We simply cannot talk of individual logics or thought models not because we
disapprove of such but because it is not possible. If it is possible at all, it cannot
be known therefore, it is not possible! To account for the existence of a principle
of intelligibility there must be at least a relationship or communication between
two parties, with recourse to one entity alone, anything trumped up cannot be
said to be logical. So, it is simply impossible to have individual thought models.
At the extreme, it is only group-based logics or thought models that are possible.
In this constitutes the wedge of limitation which postmodernism cannot cross.
In this essay, we want to look at what logic and postmodernism are in
their own right as disciplines. Then, we shall take a brief look at logic and
postmodern thinking identifying some postmodern logical systems. We shall
attempt to propose a formalist method that could be described as postmodern in a
bid to develop and promote a non-axiomatic method for logic. This represents a
radical break from the popular tradition in which modern logic, also known as
mathematical logic has effectively become a branch of mathematics. An attempt
to establish the independence of logic from mathematics could not be any less
postmodern. It may interest the reader to know that the backbone of
postmodernism is broken only by logic because postmodernism itself is a type of
logic.
Logic and Postmodernism: Conceptual Clarification
Logic read simply, constitutes principles of intelligibility. It enables us to
distinguish correct reasoning from an incorrect one. The bases of this correctness
are the laws of thought and other logical principles and rules that derive their
force from them. A reasoning/proof is therefore correct if it abides by the
provisions of these laws and it is incorrect if it breaks any of them. Correctness
and incorrectness as we employ them here could be treated as synonyms for
intelligibility and unintelligibility. Here, a correct reasoning could be described
as intelligible whereas an incorrect one could be described as unintelligible.
Between two interlocutors, A and B, there are four possible intelligibility
positions that must hold namely:
(i) A and B understand themselves in the form of anti-symmetry relation i.e.
Rxy ∧ Ryx ⊃ x = y. Here, that the conversations from A and B to each
other are intelligible to each is due to the fact that they employ the same
logic which they both understand its rules.
Page91
(ii) That one of A and B pretends that the conversations from the other is not
intelligible to him, whereas in actuality it is, i.e. they both employ the
same logic and do understand its rules. This relation is asymmetric i.e.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
Rxy ⊃ ~Ryx. This relation is forced because one party pretends not to
understand the other. This sort of thing happens every day in situations
where one person wants to score undue advantage over another.
(iii) That one of A and B genuinely does not understand the rules of the
logic employed by another. This relation is non-symmetric i.e. (~Rxy
⊃ Ryx) ˅ ~Rxy. This occurs any time people from two different
cultures work together.
(iv) That A and B understand themselves in the form of symmetric relation
i.e. Rxy ⊃ Ryx. Here, one is able to understand the other though they
each employ different logics but each is versed in the principles and
rules of the other’s logic. This usually occurs between two people from
different cultures but who are versed in each other’s culture. For
example, a Chinese who spent years doing his university studies in
America and an American who spent years doing cultural research in
China. Although, they may each employ logical nuances from their
traditions in their conversations, it is possible for each to understand the
other. What I have done in the preceding is simply to show that logic is
the principle of intelligibility. The motor through which individuals in a
given culture understand themselves and members from different
cultures understand themselves. Language1 is properly a motor or
medium of communication of thoughts that occurs before
understanding. However, implicit in all means of communication in any
culture is logic which makes such intelligible. Just as the Indian and the
Igbo may speak English which has its logic as their common bond of
intelligibility; they each have their separate indigenous languages with
their background logics.
While postmodernism can be defined as an anti theoretic theory which
objects to the existence of an absolute standard yet, it is in itself an absolute
standard. Thus it is a thorough-going self referential theory, whose rejection of
every theory is a rejection of itself.
Postmodernism is an en fanterrible that emerged in the late 20th century.
For the most part, it is a thorn in the flesh of modern theorists. All
metadiscourses are dismissed as false testimonies and a difficult position is
advocated. In one word, postmodernism has radicalized thought, offered license
Page92
1
. I am not unaware that spoken language is not the only medium of
communication but communication through whichever medium precedes
understanding.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
of tenability to every opinion and thus ostracized standard. Paul Crowther notes
that “every age has its special verity. In the case of ‘post modernity’ this takes
the form of an emphatic relativism (in all spheres of knowledge and value) which
posits itself as a radical break with the foundationalist and utopian traditions of
the modern intellectual world” (1). What this means is that postmodernism
simply radicalized relativism and individualism and then applied them to all
spheres of knowledge – even science. In a post-modern world, truth and reality
are individually shaped by personal history, social class, gender, culture and
religion. These factors, according to postmodern thinking, combine to shape the
narratives and meanings of our lives as culturally embedded, localized social
constructions without any universal application.
As a term, Gary Aylesworth writes that ‘post modernism’ first entered
the philosophical lexicon in 1979, with the publication of the [Postmodern
Condition …] by Jean-François Lyotard. In this book, Lyotard defines
postmodernism thus: simplifying to the extreme, I define postmodern as
incredulity toward metanarratives. This incredulity is undoubtedly a product of
progress in the sciences: but that progress in turn presupposes it. To the
obsolescence of the metanarrative apparatus of legitimating corresponds, most
notably, the crisis of metaphysical philosophy and of the university institution
which in the past relied on it. The narrative function is losing its functions, its
great hero, its great dangers, its great voyages, its great goal (xxiv).
What Lyotard means here is that postmodernism emerged as an
opposition to the absolutist standards of modernism, the implication of which is
the erosion of vital tools of development among intellectual and non-intellectual
cultures. There is a delicate note here which Lyotard pronounced later. It is the
position that the postmodern also presuppose the modern. Lyotard (79) declares
that the postmodern is undoubtedly a part of the modern. “A work can become
modern only if it is first postmodern. Postmodernism thus understood is not
modernism at its end but in the nascent state, and this state is constant” (79).
On the whole, following from the conception of postmodernism above,
we may regard the Ududo formalist method we propose in this essay as a
postmodern reactionary to the orthodox axiomatic method. Also, the Ezumezu
logical system just like the other non-standard logics we shall discuss are forms
of postmodern thinking focusing on alternatives and disestablishing any absolute
standard for thought.
Post Modern Logics
Page93
Logic describes correct reasoning as well as sensible propositions. What is meant
here is that logic not only distinguishes correct reasoning from incorrect
reasoning, it also distinguishes sensible proposition from nonsensical ones. In
this wise we talk of the form of logic and its subject matter. The formalization of
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
logic since the 19th century, as laudable as it is, has also impoverished its
philosophical content (MACFARLANE 2002). Logicians now work with strings
of symbols aimed principally to achieving mathematical precision. But to the
extent, they have advanced hopes in this direction; logic has to the same extent
suffered in terms of content. Even when symbols are created for the semantic
content, they are almost, always employed without recourse to any propositions
they purportedly evaluate. Thus, the race to increase the so-called expressive
power of logic has led to a post-modern radicalization of the instrument of logic.
First, it has become too mathematical and less philosophical; second, many and
different types of logics like fuzzy, paraconsistent, dialectic, many and multi
valued logics, etc, have emerged to distemper and disquiet logic as a consistent
instrument of research.
These variant logics could be post-modernist where post modern logic
itself could be formless and with infinite value range. So we can talk of some
types of logics like the ones mentioned above as post modernist in structure and
we can also talk of another type that we can call post modern logic. This latter
type is formless and infinite in values. It is what undergirds the postmodern
mantra of radical relativization which Paul Feyerabend eulogized with the phrase
“Anything goes” (28). When deployed in any area it quickly radicalizes it by
upsetting the inherent standard, norms and laws and heralds the introduction of
anarchy. For want of a better expression, the business of science, its methods and
direction when brought under the influence of this post modern logic have been
described as epistemologically anarchistic (FEYERABEND 23 – 28). As
Feyerabend notes:
The idea that science can, and should, be run according to fixed and
universal rules, is both unrealistic and pernicious. It is unrealistic, for it
takes too simple a view of the talents of man and of the circumstances
which encourage, or cause, their development. And it is pernicious, for
the attempt to enforce the rules is bound to increase our professional
qualifications at the expense of our humanity. (295)
What Feyerabend and other anarchists of the postmodern orientation promote is
a world that runs on a postmodern logic of free, dynamic, relative and
unrestricted modes of thought. It is these sorts of thought models that we here
describe as postmodern logics.
Page94
Paraconsistent logic: This is a type of non-standard logic where the
contradiction of a variable does not result in express affirmation of any other
opposing variable. In that case, the process is not trivialized by a form of
necessity that warrants the assertion of any variable. For this, the negation
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
limination or the absurdity rule popularly called ex falso quadlibet in Latin does
not hold in paraconsistent logic. This is the rule of such form:
P
~P
q
From the apparent contradiction of P and ~ P, the affirmation of any other
variable seems necessary or inevitable. Paraconsistent logic makes this triviality
to fail by its internal dynamics which permits contradictions to be true or
contradictory variables of the form A ∧ ~ A to be both true. This is a postmodern
form of reasoning in that it neglects the laws of thought. For that also, it is called
a non-standard logic with reference to the laws of thought. One of the chief
proponents of this logic is Graham Priest.
Page95
e
Relevance logic: This is also called relevant logic and it is a product of the
Australia tradition where A. R. Anderson and N. Belnap (1975) S. Read (1988)
etc., contributed much to its development. It simply insists that much more is
required for validity of arguments of the form p ⊃ q where P is the antecedent of
the conclusion q, p necessarily has to be relevant to q or that the negation of q be
inconsistent with p (MAUTNER 480-81). The inspiration behind the workers of
this logic is the need to guard against the paradoxes of material implication.
Relevance logic is therefore a non-standard logic since it insists that the form of
argument must imply its subject matter.
Many-valued logic: This is also called multi-valued. It is the more
comprehensive of the non-standard logics because it comprises all logics of the
form of truth-value gap i.e. neither true nor false and truth-value glut i.e. both
true and false. This means that all the logics with the value range of three to the
infinitely numerable fall into this bracket. This also implies the degree theoretic
semantic systems i.e. systems whose value range start from T complete truth to F
complete false.
Ezumezu logic: This is another form of non-standard logic developed in the
African tradition chiefly by J. O. Chimakonam. Its value range is three where
propositions receive three designate values one complete and two incomplete
values namely ½ representing (incomplete) truth 0/2 representing (incomplete)
falsity and then in-between them 2/2 representing both true and false which is
complete. This form of reasoning arises in African ontology where being is
conceived to have two components, concrete and non-concrete, the absence of
any component renders it incomplete. This logic also prevents exfalso quadlibet
from holding.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
Fuzzy logic: This is a non-standard logic that is sometimes referred to as Degree
theoretic semantic because of its perchance for fragmenting value range in
degrees. In it, propositions of a system are assigned values in real numbers like in
Boolean Algebra. The two basic assignments are 1 and 0. Whereas 1 represents
complete truth, 0 represents complete falsity. The next values assigned in fuzzy
logic besides these two are in degrees which are not necessarily complete. These
degree values are strictly greater than 0 and strictly less than 1 and are adjudged
partially true. Some traditions sometimes interpret them as partially false. For
example between 1 and 0, we can have ½, 1/3, 1/4, 1/5, 1/6, etc., and since it is
not mathematically sensible to replicate subdivisions of 0 in this way, the value
range are regarded as various degrees of truth hence partially true and not
partially false.
Postmodern logic: It may surprise the reader that the systems discussed above
are referred to as postmodern logics; why is there yet another called postmodern
logic? What is the difference? They all have the same orientation in that they are
non-standard logics with variants of truth range but the properly postmodern has
an infinite value range above all else. So, one may also call it infinite-valued
logic, or I-valued logic or I-logic as the case may be with the letter I representing
infinity.
I shall like to credit this logic to Paul Feyerabend who brought out the
extreme radicalization of postmodern thinking. In his popular against method he
advocates epistemological anarchism or anarchistic science (21). In his words,
“All methodologies have their limitations and the only rule that survives is
anything goes” (296). This implies infinity of values in any language fragmented
in degrees of truth whose converse i.e. degrees of falsity is also admissible. In
other words, in adopting the real numbers θ and N we shall have θ representing
degrees of falsity and N representing degrees of infinite truth range. In this logic,
there is no such thing as completely false or completely true. Every statement is
partially true and of course, partially false. The difference however lies in the
degrees of truth and falsity. The postmodern logic is described by contexts such
that value range changes from point to point in simple infinity.
Page96
One other thing about postmodern logic is that for every range of infinite
values represented by the real numbers, there is no cardinality property attached.
Put differently, no real number of partially false has a one-to-one correspondence
with any real number of the range of partially true, hence simple infinity. For the
great insight from Paul Feyerabend I shall like to christen the postmodern logic,
Feyerebend logic. There are many other variants that could be described as
postmodern logics besides the ones described above which for want of space, we
could not discuss here. Some of such include dialethic logic, partial logic, four
valued logic, etc.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
Why a Formalist Method for Logic?
The Igbo term Ududo simply means spider. Ududo reasoning as the name goes
refers to the spider’s web or web-like reasoning procedure. This becomes the
type of reasoning mechanism we wish to project in this essay. It is postmodernist
because it represents a break from modern logic in its designation of alternative
proof apparatus. To reason may not be exactly the same thing as to prove as some
logicians notably Gilbert Harman (107) insists, but proofs no matter how
elementary involves a certain form of reasoning. One need to be able to move
from premise to premise in the process of conducting a proof and in this is found
reasoning of some type. Ududo reasoning as used here is additionally a kind of
proof. Thus, it offers us a formalist proof apparatus to show whether a given
argument is valid and sound or not without any axiomatic process—this also
reflects the property of postmodern thinking. Logic therefore can be
unaxiomatized. The one implication of modern development of western logic is
that logic became lured into matrimony with mathematics such that whether
mathematics can be given foundation in logic (Frege’s logicism) or logic adopts
the formal structure and axiomatic method of mathematics (Hilbert’s formalism)
remain permanently potential and tentatively actual in respective order. For this,
modern western logic therefore becomes properly speaking, mathematical logic.
A delusion is thus setting in because at the purest development of logic, there is a
growing impossibility to talk of logic without mathematics or to simply say logic
without the adjective mathematical. The basic reason for this delusion is the
adoption of higher mathematical methods like axiomatization beginning in the
17th century with writers like George Boole, Charles Pierce, Gucippe Peano,
Gottrifried Leibniz and then reaching perfection in Gottlob Frege, Bertrand
Russell and Alfred-North Whitehead.
What we are out to achieve with Ududo reasoning is partly to return
logic to logicians. In offering a non-axiomatized proof of arguments, even at the
quantification level, Ududo reasoning procedure shows that there can be an
unpolluted formalist method for logic in diagrammatic expressions of our
reasoning. Note of course, that formalist method refers to a method of proof that
is non-axiomatic i.e. structurally derived with nothing more than rules of thumb
which serves as mere guide or explanatory tool to proof, whereas formal
structure refers to the symbolic language in proof construction; the latter is a
framework for both axiomatic and formalist methods of proof. We may therefore
study mathematical logic as a branch of logic rather than the next inescapable
stage in the development of our discipline.
Page97
It is imperative to clearly subsume mathematical logic to a bigger
shadow of logic without mathematical method. Terms for example are defined
functionally and function is characterized by method. In this way, modern logic
which adopts mathematical method becomes subsumed under mathematics and is
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
hardly a discipline in its own right or at least a properdeutic or instrument to
philosophy. Tongues have even begun to wag; Richard Kaye wrote a text book
on logic recently and chose to title it The Mathematics of Logic (2007).
According to him, mathematical logic has been in existence as a recognized
branch of mathematics for over a hundred years. Its methods and theorems have
shown their applicability not just to philosophical studies in the foundations of
mathematics which is perhaps their original raison d’être but also to mainstream
mathematics itself (vii). The stressed phrase signifies the original status of logic
as a tool of philosophy but which has been transformed to mathematical logic as
a branch of mathematics. Our point is that the adoption of mathematical method
(axiomatic) in the business of logic for close to one hundred years now portrays it
as a branch of mathematics.
The generally accepted theory is that the basic characteristic of logic is
that logic should be about reasoning or deduction, and should attempt to provide
rules for valid inferences. These rules which should be sufficiently and precisely
defined become rules for manipulating strings of symbols. These strings of
symbols should also have attached meanings since they are according to Leibniz
in his Calculus philosophicus or Ratiocinator, a Lingua Characterica or what
Frege in his [Begriffsschrift] calls a formula language for pure thought. In it,
every well formed formula represents at least a sentence and every sentence
Frege notes in his “The Thought: a Logical Inquiry” has a sense or meaning. The
challenge here is that through the meanings of symbols, a logician should try to
present a logical justification for the inference rules which ought to be
demonstrations that express the hidden or intuitive structures of our reasoning.
But contrary-wise, with the metamorphosis to mathematical logic, what the
logician attempts to do in proofs of arguments is present a mathematical
justification of the rules of logic given the axiomatic method of mathematics i.e.
some pre-established axioms are appealed to whose semantic contents are merely
formal other than material in generating a proof such that we therefore say that a
sentence is formally true without wishing to say it is actually true.
Page98
The application of mathematics to logic (mathematical logic) led to the
emergence of two interpretive theorems namely soundness and completeness
theorems. The soundness theorem states that no incorrect deductions can be made
from the inference rules if we take “correct” to mean the meanings of our
sentences. The completeness theorem on the other hand states that every correct
deduction that can be expressed in the system can actually be made using a
combination of the inference rules provided. The first theorem calls for the proof
of consistency and non-compatibility of the individual rules of inference
(assuming them to be axiomatic), while the second calls for the proof of
completeness of the system (again, assuming such system to be axiomatic).
These two therefore become mathematical theorems because to prove them, there
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
is a need for an algorithm. So we see how logic grows from being a discipline or
tool of philosophy to a branch of mathematics simply by adopting the method of
mathematics.
Much as an eclectic optimist may claim that the journey of modern logic
into mathematics has been fruitful, the fact remains to be disputed that every
future development of logic would inevitably be a footnote to a development in
mathematics. This is a muffling of a discipline into a theory in another discipline
and a stifling of its independent progress. David Hilbert writes that “as long as a
branch of science offers an abundance of problems, so long is it alive; a lack of
problems foreshadows extinction or the cessation of independent development”
(407). The subsumation of logic under mathematics foreshadows extinction to its
independent development. This is because its concerns and its problems would
ultimately be those of mathematics without any independent focus.
Our call here for a return to deduction and induction and maybe their
advanced development as logical methods rather than the blind embrace and
adoption of mathematical method is worth a second thought by any logician. The
impression this creates is that logic is losing ground to mathematics. It is not out
of place to adopt a mathematical method in a satellite development of our
discipline but it would be out of place to make it the central and sole method of
logic. A nervy implication to this is that the future development of logic would
be determined by the developments in mathematics. We have seen the Cantor’s
continuum, the Diophantine equation, the Fermat’s problem, the Hilbert’s
compatibility of mathematical axioms to mention a few becoming the occupation
of logicians after the mathematicians had laid them to rest or at least given them
the full measure of their strength. Therefore, to do as little as discover or advance
own methods for modern logic would not only restore the disciplinary status of
logic but would open it up to measures of parallel development with other
disciplines. Under this influence, logicians would be able to plot an open, broad
view and independent development of their subject and get to a stage at which
they would find an economically viable career in it.
Ududo Reasoning as a Postmodern Formalist Method for Logic
Page99
Disorganization that leads to organization is the way of a spider. Sometimes, we
reason from seemingly disorganized premise but in the end arrive at an organized
conclusion. Let us first define reasoning following Gilbert Harman (107) as a
logical procedure for revising our beliefs, changing our views and which
determines which new beliefs we acquire and which old ones we set aside (where
the procedure referred to above simply means a set of axiomatic rules or
formalist rules). This therefore, does not exclude non-axiomatic procedures like
formalist structures which employ simple non-axiomatic rules in putting thoughts
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
into logical perspectives; insights into the latter are actually the main thrust of
this essay.
The relationship between reasoning and logic in African thought is
cordial in that reasoning functions as a tool of logic while logic remains a
framework for reasoning hence reasoning is considered rigorous if it is logical.
Being logical roughly speaking simply means adherence to laid down axioms,
formalist rules and other logical laws in the arrangement of thought.
In their thought system, Africans of different tribal backgrounds believe
and hold the view that reality exists in a network of interconnection. This is why
their ontology makes most of the collectivity rather than the particular; and group
identity rather than individual identity. One exists only in a group; to be
ostracized is to cease to exist. Let us remember also that in African thought
variables are concrete realities and not abstract signs, so they too are in a network
of interconnection with the operators bringing them in contact. This means that
variables that are not connected through one operator could be connected through
another.
Ideally, the Ududo or Cobweb is one framework of logical reasoning
which captures the African idea of interconnection of realities in a non-axiomatic
way. Thus using it as a framework for reasoning, Ududo shows how our beliefs
and views are related, how we acquire new ones, how we set aside old ones and
how we place them in proper logical perspectives. The ones we set aside we may
reacquire and the ones we acquire we may set aside later as contexts and
circumstances demand. Below is an example of Ududo reasoning:
Unquantified argument structure
D Q
Q C
C ∧ Q D
: . (D ∧ Q) ∨ (C ∧ Q)
Page100
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
Here we start reasoning with the first term placed at the centre
of a circle within a square box thereafter other terms could be
placed in any type of box other than a square and the uniformity
of each box maintained throughout. This is to give direction to
the reasoning. In Ududo reasoning every operator is represented
with a unique type of arrow for example: becomes ,
,turns to ; ∧ becomes or ;∨ becomes or ; ~ turns
to or , ⇔ becomes ; while signifies a drop down of
a unary variable. Additional rule of the thumb is that inferences
of wedged-implication are ideally done towards the right while
those of wedged-reduction are done towards the left to ensure
clarity. Also or or or signify therefore or conclusion.
Fig. 1: Diagram of ududo reasoning
C
Q
D
Page101
Valid and sound:
C
Q
We see that this argument is sound because the premises are relevant to the
conclusion. The premise C wedge-reduces to Q has an arrow connection to the
first premise D wedge-implies Q. But the fact that the first premise does not
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
connect directly to the second in that order also shows that the argument is
inconsistent therefore valid. Relevance primarily determines soundness. Ududo
reasoning thus is a viable apparatus for determining the soundness of arguments
from a formalist perspective. For an argument to be sound the arrows must
connect the premises and the conclusion and for it to be valid, the connection of
the arrows must not be properly ordered. This reasoning format therefore
succinctly exposes and clarifies the muddy case of validity without soundness.
Quantified argument structure:
GHy Jy ∧ Dy
KWx Bx Cx
GBz ~ Jz ∨ ~ Cz
:. GHy (Dy ∧ ~ Jy) ∨ (Bx ∧ ~ Cz)
Fig. 2: Diagram of quantified argument structure
KW
D J
Y
X
Z
Page102
Valid & Sound:
GB
B
C
GH
Here we begin by placing the quantifiers in triangles at the left, right and then the
bottom sides of the Ududo. Note also that in line with the reasoning pattern of
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
Ezumezu logic, the group comes first before the individual hence the KW, GH
and GB take placement in this order.
Evaluated argument structure (improper)
1.
2.
3.
T (J K)
T (Q ∧ J)
F (K) :. (Q ∧ K) (J ∧ K)
Fig. 3: Diagram of evaluated argument structure
#
#
K
Q
*
J
J
*
Our variables are J, K*, Q, K#
Page103
*
*
K
Valid & Sound.
In the above, we use * to designate true prepositions and # to designate false ones
while “C” would designate the complemented proposition. The argument is
sound in that there are arrow connections which show the relevance of the
premises to the conclusion and it is valid in that line two shows inconsistency in
the ordering of the arrow connections. To be well-ordered line one would have to
connect line two and not the other way round. The major operator in the
conclusion is true because where the agbọ-ochie is false and the agbọ-ọhụụ
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
true, Ezumezu logic shows that the wedged-implication is true due to the
principle of existential possibility. In the conclusion lines indicated by , the
agbọ-ochie Q ∧ K is false because one of the ejima K# is already shown to be
false, and the agbọ-ọhụụ J ∧ K is true because an established premise
J k already shows the variables to be true. Note however that this is not a
full-blooded argument in Ezumezu logic because it is not properly evaluated. A
properly evaluated argument in Ezumezu logic must have three values because
Ezumezu-African logic is strictly three-valued.
Conclusion
This Ududo proof apparatus is therefore formalist in method since it is devoid of
axioms. It is also postmodernist in structure since it portends a non-standard
logical system in the mold of Ezumezu logic. Generally, it retains symbolism but
takes it to a new level with the introduction of graphics. The graphics then by
their involvement draws logic closer to subject matter while not tearing it apart
from form. It is in exercises like this that the subject of modern logic would be
redefined as a discipline rather than as a branch of mathematics. Hence, Ududo
reasoning can be described as a formalist method with a postmodernist flare. The
goal of this essay therefore was to propose a formalist method for logic that is at
the same time postmodernist in keeping with the postmodern ideal of creating
alternative frameworks and breeching the walls of static hegemonies in thought.
Relevant Literature
1. AYLESWORTH, Gary. “Postmodernism”, [Stanford Encyclopedia
of Philosophy, Edward Zalta, Ed.], Published Fri. Sep. 30, 2005.
Retrieved Mon. 12 Sept. 2011 8:07 pm. Web.
Page104
2. CROWTHER, Paul. [Against Method: Outline of an Anarchistic
Theory of Knowledge], 1975. New Left Books: London.
Paperback.
3. FEYERABEND, Paul K. [Against Method], 1975. Verso Press:
New York. Paperback.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
4. --- . “Against Method”, [The Canon and its Critics: A Multi
perspective Introduction to Philosophy Furman, Todd and Mitchell
Avila Ed.], pp346-354, 2000. Mayfield: California.
5. HARMAN, Gilbert. “Logic and Reasoning”, [Synthese], pp107
127, 60 1984. Paperback.
6. Hilbert, David. “Mathematical Problems”. [Bulletin (New Series)
of the American Mathematical Society], 37. 407 – 436. Reprinted
from Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. 8 (1902): 437-470. Paperback.
7. Kaye, Richard. [The Mathematics of Logic. A Guide to
Completeness Theorem and Their Applications], 2007. Cambridge
University Press: Cambridge. Paperback.
8. LYOTARD, Jean-Francois. [The Postmodern Condition: A Report
on Knowledge, Trans. Geoff Benningon and Brian Massumi],
1983. Theory and History of Literature Vol. 10 Manchester
University Press: Manchester. Paperback.
9. MACFARLANE, John. “Frege, Kant,and the Logic in Logicism”.
[The Philosophical Review], pp25-61, Vol 111. No 1. Jan., 2002.
Paperback.
10. MAUTNER, Thomas. [The Penguin Dictionary of Philosophy],
2002. Penguin: London. Paperback.
11. OZUMBA Godfrey and CHIMAKONAM Jonathan.
Page105
“Postmodernism and the Development of Political Science”,
[Political Science: An Introductory Reader, BASSEY Celestine. O
and OZUMBA G. O. Ed.], pp86-108, 2012. Concept Publications:
Lagos. Paperback.
Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and Religions
THE PREFIX “AFRICAN” AND ITS IMPLICATION FOR
PHILOSOPHY IN AFRICA
Samuel T. SEGUN, MA
Department of Philosophy
University of Calabar, Calabar.
Abstract
Philosophy today is often regionalized unlike science and other disciplines. Thus
we talk of Western, Eastern, American and African Philosophy. To speak or
write philosophy within the ambit of the prefix “African” would elicit two major
responses. First is the affirmative response which believes that indeed there exists
some form of philosophy in Africa although distinct from Western philosophy in
approach, procedure and methods but not in kind. The second is the denialist
response which rejects vehemently the position of the former; in that they deny
the existence of African philosophy independent of Western colouration. In other
words, they do not believe that there exists any form of philosophy distinct from
the Western idea of philosophy be it in approach or method. Within this frame
certain problems arise such as the problem of interpretation or definition, the
myth of unanimity and the problem of ethnophilosophy. The aim of this work
thus is to understand the implications of the prefix “African” for philosophy in
Africa. In this attempt, we uncover the subject of African Philosophy, its many
possibilities, nature and interpretations. In understanding the implications of the
prefix “African” for philosophy in Africa, the work avers that the affirmative
response in modern times is an advocacy for what Chimakonam refers to as
systematic African philosophy; and the denialist response to the subject is an
outright rejection of the universal character of philosophy. For the laws of logic,
the burden of axiology, the questions of metaphysics, the problems of socio
political philosophy and the concerns of epistemology all transcend geographical
boundaries.
Keywords: Affirmative, Denialist, Philosophy, African, African Philosophy,
Ethnophilosophy, Systematic African Philosophy, Complementarity, Unanimity.
Introduction
No scholarly write up I believe, can sufficiently exhaust the subject of
philosophy in Africa. The prefix “African” when discussed alongside philosophy
in Africa appropriately, presupposes the subject of African Philosophy. It
designates the presence of philosophy within the continent of Africa. We must
note that philosophy in Africa “means more than African Philosophy… [it refers
to] the activities of doing, writing and teaching philosophy in Africa”
(MAKINDE 2000, 103). As direct as this may sound it has with it attendant
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
implications. The first of such implications which we shall discuss extensively in
this work is the myth of unanimity. Second is the problem of equating the prefix
African to a race or to the colour black or more appropriately Negro Africa. This
was the challenge Leopold Senghor had to contend with in his later days when
his concept of negritude was misconstrued to mean the Negro (black) race. Third
is a conflict when we discuss philosophy in the context of geographical enclaves.
The aim here is to question, what makes a philosophy Western, Eastern,
American or African? Does philosophy change in its nature and content within
cultural frames? What are the roles of geographical categorization and the
content of philosophy? Fourth, there is the question of the relevance of
ethnophilosophy and if it is an integral and indispensible part of African
Philosophy and indeed philosophy in Africa.
As we look through different societies the content of their investigations
with regards to philosophy may greatly differ in context but not in content. Much
like when we refer to Philosophy in Britain, we are probing into the how
philosophy is done in Britain. Likewise discussing the nature of philosophy in
Africa is to question the study, teaching, writing and doing of philosophy in
Africa. African philosophy as an academic study is relatively new and is often
studied alongside African Studies as a mere subset. But this is not sufficient to
appraise the quality of philosophy in Africa. Unfortunately but thankfully
attempts are been made to ensure that academic or professional African
Philosophy is studied and taught in African Universities. Prior to this attempt,
philosophy students in Africa have been literally taught Western Philosophy from
undergraduate to postgraduate levels. It was a hectic and tiring journey through
debates, conferences and publications for African Philosophy to earn a place in
the league of global philosophies. Thus, “African Philosophy as a component of
academic global philosophy has become very respectable in its contributions to
shaping the history and experiences of the African people and that work on
African Philosophy must be persistent and sustained” (MESEMBE 2013, 122).
Let us proceed to unravel the subject matter of this article accordingly; (i)
Understanding the Prefix “African” (ii) Philosophy in Africa and African
Philosophy (iii) Implications of the Prefix “African” for Philosophy in Africa and
(iv) Understanding African Philosophy through a unified explanation.
Understanding the Prefix “African”
The prefix African refers to one with an African origin. It also refers to anything
relating to Africa or Africans. It is expedient to note that in current times there
has been a misconception that Africa is a country rather than a continent of many
people. This has sparked tremendous reactions from Africans. Although the
purpose of this may not be really known in that it could purely be an honest
mistake or a calculated attempt to disposes a people of a place in global
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
advancement. Whatever the reasons are, they are of little consequence to our
discourse. More so, Western anthropology has made it somewhat difficult to see
the African people as distinct people, a culmination of varying tribes and
cultures. The etymology of the word Africa may lend us some help as we
proceed:
In antiquity the Greeks are said to have called the continent Libya and the
Romans to have called it Africa, perhaps from the Latin aprica (“sunny”)
or the Greek aphrike (“without cold”). The name Africa, however, was
chiefly applied to the northern coast of the continent, which was, in effect,
regarded as a southern extension of Europe. The Romans, who for a time
ruled the North African coast, are also said to have called the area south of
their settlements Afriga, or the Land of the Afrigs—the name of a Berber
community south of Carthage. (Encyclopaedia Britannica 2011, Web.,
NP).
From its etymology we must note that Africa is a continent of people beyond
Negro Africans. In fact the etymology of the word in no way referred to Negros.
The prefix “African” therefore refers to a person from the continent of Africa.
During the scramble for Africa, it is said that “Europe’s new colonial
territories enclosed hundreds of diverse and independent groups, with no
common history, culture, language or religion” (MEREDITH 2005, 1-2). There
after the division of these territories led to the formation of many failed and
failing states, historic genocides, ethnic clashes and cleansing, toggle for power
and ethnic superiority etc. Thus the failure to see Africa or understand the prefix
“African” from that perspective of independent groups could be counter
productive to fulfilling the aim of this work. Uduma notes strongly the words of
Gene Blocker, the “word African means in the style of but they can also mean
“within the geographical area of”. There also appears to be a third sense which is
a “person of”. In the context of this third sense, on can still act or write in the
“style of” or be “within the geographical area of” Africa…” (2014, 128). From
all the above definitions, readers can glean that the prefix African refers to a
person from the continent, an appurtenance of Africa, and the style of. It is within
this frame of possible definition that our navigation in exploring this essay can be
actualized.
Philosophy in Africa and African Philosophy
To discuss philosophy in Africa is one thing and African Philosophy another.
Philosophy in Africa refers to Africa’s participation in the universal enterprise of
philosophy while African Philosophy presupposes a distinct way of doing
philosophy. It differs from Western, Eastern or American philosophy not in kind
but in approach. What do we then mean when we say we are doing philosophy?
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
What is philosophy? The process of rational and critical reflection is the process
of doing philosophy. And philosophy is the system that makes this reflection
possible. In other words philosophy is a reflective investigation into the nature of
things. As Ezeani puts it:
To philosophize is to think, and to think is to question. To philosophize is
to ask questions and question the answer to the question and continue the
process until one arrives at the ultimate answer- the truth… through the
process of critical questioning and reflection the philosopher attempts to
confront his or her existence, assumptions and also contribute to the
development of thoughts. (EZEANI 2005, 11 and 7)
To deny the African this right and by this I mean the right to think is not only to
question his rationality but to question his humanity and existence. Having
established what qualifies as philosophy it becomes absurd when the question is
there a philosophy in Africa is asked. For when we refer to philosophy in Europe
or Asia, we are simply probing into how philosophy is done in Europe or Asia.
Likewise discussing the nature of philosophy in Africa is to question the study,
teaching, writing and practice of philosophy in Africa. The question itself
appears to be self-contradictory for it appears that asking if there is a philosophy
in Africa presupposes the following; first that there exists an African philosophy
at least mentally- for a thing is insofar as it can be imagined, “second, (to
question its) meaning, third, (its) content/nature and finally, (its) relevance”
(ASIRA 2004, 197). In discussing philosophy in Africa we must necessarily
discuss African Philosophy. Thankfully, “the debate or controversy on whether
or not there is an African philosophy is dead and buried. At best it is a matter of
mere historical interest” (UDUIGWOMEN 2009, 2).
African Philosophy
suggests to us a “contextualized critical thinking of or a philosophical product by
an African… it is (or part of it is) an articulation by an African philosopher of his
or her ideas or thoughts in a coded format meant to provide an answer to a mind
boggling question or a solution to a contextualized social or political problem”
(EZEANI 2005, 9). In the recent past African Philosophy has had her share of
debates all tailored towards deconstructing her growing trends, ideas and
influence; the problem of method, logic, criticality, etc., all featured prominently
in deconstructivists arguments. But we must encourage African philosophy
practitioners “…to do [philosophy] in the way they think it should be done
including of course, the writing and teaching of it” (MAKINDE 2000, 125). By
African Philosophy we suggest a philosophy done by Africans through reflecting
on their existential ambience. Bodunrin summarizes African philosophy as “the
philosophy done by African philosophers whether it be in the area of logic, ethics
or history of philosophy” (SOGOLO 1993, 2). As put forward by Sodipo, “when
you say African philosophy you are drawing attention to that aspect of
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
philosophy which arises from a special problem and the unique experience of
African people” (UDUIGWOMEN 2009, 6). An exegesis of the above definition
suggests to us that African philosophy is utilizing the tools of philosophy to
explain reality from the African perspective. Asukwo defines African philosophy
as “a subjective world-view packaged and anchored with the mind-frame in order
to ask and answer questions that can solve the immediate problem at hand within
a given socio-economic and political environment” (2009, 30).
As is the main function of philosophy being the search for truth in its
entirety (NZE 1990, 44), African philosophers must maintain this disposition if
we must grow the influence of African philosophy. In fact, it is worthy to revamp
the notion that African philosophy does not differ in kind or degree (in terms of
hierarchy) or quality from Western or any other philosophy. They only differ in
their approaches and investigation of truth. It is often argued as did Ozumba and
Chimakonam that whereas Western thought is exclusive and dichotomized in
nature, African thought is complementary, integrative and inclusive (2014, 80
85). The above corroborates our argument that Western and African philosophies
differ in approach but not in kind. Chimakonam in his work “Why can’t there be
an African Logic?” explains further:
…among the characteristics of African logic is the uniqueness of its
approach. Western logician for instance, takes the middle position
between A and B and only asserts one when he has fully drawn out his
proof. The African logician however, asserts one A and B before drawing
out his proof to justify this position. This is principally why, by the
standard of western logic any such reasoning pattern is said to be guilty
of bias and prejudice and is accused of lacking in objectivity. It is by this
standard that African thought pattern is said to be illogical. (2011, 143)
What this means is that African philosophy or in the above case African logic
arrives at its philosophical depth and identity through a rather different route,
distinct from that applied in Western philosophy. The tenets of African
philosophy “may legitimately be found in the types of literature mentioned
earlier, and that its fundamental conceptual framework and content may be
profitable compared with “Western philosophy” on some grounds, at least”
(WRIGHT 1984, 53). In corroboration of the above, Oyeshile notes “Hence, we
submit that what African philosophy is, involves the application of … conceptual
analysis, logic, criticism and synthesis to the reflections on issues that are of
paramount importance to the African needs and ways of life” (2008, 62). To
further buttress the position of this work, the above arguments insist not just on
the necessity of African philosophy but on its uniqueness.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
Implications of the Prefix “African” for Philosophy in Africa
When we mention philosophy in Africa, two distinct responses are most likely to
be heard. These two responses form what this work refers to as the denialist and
affirmative opinions. The denialists argue that there is no philosophy in Africa.
The African, they presume, is incapable of philosophizing. On the other hand the
affirmatives agree that there is not only philosophy in Africa, there is also a thing
known as African philosophy in the sense that we speak of Western philosophy.
When philosophy is used alongside the prefix “African” what must come to mind
is the universality of the subject matter of philosophy which cuts across
independent groups, with no common history, culture, language or religion
within the continent of Africa. The unfortunate conditioning of Western minds by
anthropological literature and those of Africans by colonial indoctrination have
led to a loss of individuality with regards to philosophy in Africa. We shall
address certain problems this may engineer such as the myth of unanimity,
ethnophilosophy and the categorization of Africa as a race or color.
The Myth of Unanimity
The Myth of Unanimity is founded on a misguided anthropological finding and
belief. For there appears to be a sort of unified way of thinking, cultural response,
sense of right and wrong and in this case philosophy when Western
anthropologists, and many African writers express their opinions. We often hear
things such as, “we Africans, the Africans” as though a uniformed way of
thinking was common place in Africa. This does not exist in itself. It is rather a
misconception of a people assumed to be one in thought and culture. To aptly
capture this, Temples’ work on the Bantus was an attempt to impose the findings
of his expedition amongst the Bantus to the rest of Africa. He avers, “Anyone
who claims that primitive peoples possess no system of thought, excludes them
thereby from the category of men (1959, 14)”. Although somewhat derogatory,
by primitive people he meant Negro Africans. He simply worked on the
assumption that the Bantus being from the Negro race ultimately had things in
common with other tribes or peoples of such race. To corroborate this further,
early anthropologist and ethnographers within Africa worked with similar
assumptions. The belief was that:
The central feature of the types to which African cultures belong is that
there is a certain world-view to which can be related to all other central
concepts, including those of religion and theology, morality and social
organization. (ABRAHAM 1962, 45)
By implication, it is meant that this world-view makes African peoples similar in
thoughts patterns—a thoroughly misconstrued belief. For if it were so, African
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
traditional communities would have had no need for communal clashes because
they would have been a homogeneous people simply living in different areas but
similar in mind, thought and culture. The myth of unanimity arises when a search
for a:
…common feature, theme, structure or disposition of the African
traditional thoughts that will serve as the criterion for the Africanness of a
philosophy…(thus) the criterion for the Africanness of a philosophy is the
attempt to impose a certain metaphysics and epistemology of a certain
African peoples on the whole of Africans. (UDUMA 2014, 139)
Why this myth is dangerous to the progress of African philosophy is best
explained thus:
Behind this usage, then, there is a myth at work, the myth of primitive
unanimity, with its suggestion that in ‘primitive’ societies—that is to say,
non-Western societies—everybody agrees with everybody else. It follows
that in such societies there can never be individual beliefs or philosophies
but only collective systems of belief. (HOUNTONDJI 1983, 60)
As noted above, the damage of this claim is preposterous and an impediment to
the development of African philosophy. In sincerity we must insist, as is the case
that although certain characteristics flow across African communities, (which
ultimately form their approach to philosophy and not content) it still doesn’t
make them one people. The myth of unanimity simply is a misconstrued notion
that all Africans are alike in thought and beliefs. Thus when the prefix “African”
with regards to a philosophy is used it often would be used to refer to a people
with a common disposition to philosophy. On this myth Asouzua opines that:
…the impression is created that African philosophy is a unified body of
ideas congenial to all African societies. In this case, these worldviews do
not represent the ideas of concrete historical individuals; neither can they be
ascribed to distinct philosophical trends in the past. (2004, 111)
Since this is not the case, African philosophers are encouraged to disabuse their
minds from writing their thoughts as if it were a thought borrowed from the
community. This is thus a call for individualistic philosophy and interpretation of
reality. It is a passionate call enjoining a pursuit to hear the individual’s voice
clearly and distinctly and different from that of the community. Critics might
claim that a denial of the myth will be the denial of African philosophy. This is
not the case, for to insist that there is an African philosophy different in this
mode of operation but not in its content or kind from Western philosophy is not
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
the same as what the myth tells us. African philosophy like the other world
philosophies is confronted with matters of state, governance, beauty, art, being,
knowledge and its source, morality and moral judgements, the sequence and
validity of arguments etc. This will imply that it also concerns itself with
branches of philosophy such as logic, epistemology, metaphysics, socio-political
philosophy, ethics and aesthetics.
Ethnophilosophy and Systematic African Philosophy
When the call for evidence was made to those who argue for the existence of pre
colonial philosophy in Africa, the only way for justification was to produce the
thoughts of sages and folklores. Literature were produce by both indigenous
Africans and expatriate philosophers as means of justification. This include the
works of Temples [Bantu Philosophy], Kwasi Wiredu’s “The concept of Truth in
Akan Language”, John Mbiti and many others after them. It remains as this paper
argues that these literature were products of desperation of a people deprived of
an identity and a shared humanity.
Without a doubt, certain elements of philosophical importance can be
found in traditional African society. Their philosophical relevance are worthy of
mention. The argument against them is that they fall short of the required
criticality, structure, analysis and methods of philosophy. Ethnophilosophy is a
term used “derogatorily to refer to the works of those anthropologists,
sociologists, ethnographers and philosophers who present the collective
worldviews of the African people, their myth and folklores as philosophy”
(EGBEKE 1999, 92). Hountondji believes that ethnophilosophy is a mere
cultural philosophy. It is a poor attempt to systematize a worldview. Thus it falls
short of the necessary reflection, critique and character of philosophy.
“Ethnophilosophy is pre-philosophy mistaking itself for a metaphilosophy, a
philosophy which instead of presenting its own rational justification, shelters
lazily behind the authority of a tradition and projects its own theses and beliefs
on to that tradition” (1983, 63). The challenge of ethnophilosophy is that it
reemphasizes the myth of unanimity and does not appropriate philosophy to
philosophers themselves but rather to a people. In the realms of ethnophilosophy,
philosophy becomes a communal possession therefore losing its rigor. It is
simply a debased philosophy unworthy of the name philosophy. To buttress this
point further, Barry Hallen notes the challenges of ethnophilosophy which is best
quoted unaltered:
(1) It presents itself as a philosophy of peoples rather than of individuals.
In Africa one is therefore given the impression that there can be no
equivalents to a Socrates or a Kant. Ethnophilosophy speaks only of
Bantu philosophy, Dogon philosophy, Akan philosophy; as such its scope
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
is collective (or ‘tribal’), of the world-view variety; (2) Its sources are in
the past, in what is described as authentic, traditional African culture of
the pre-colonial variety, of the Africa prior to ‘modernity’. These can be
found in cultural by-products that were primarily oral: parables, proverbs,
poetry, songs, and myths - oral literature generally. Obviously, since such
sources do not present their ‘philosophies’ in any conventionally
discursive or technical format, it is the academic scholars, rather than
African peoples, who interpret or analyse them, and thus come up with
what they present as the systematized ‘philosophy’ of an entire African
culture; (3) From a methodological point of view, ethnophilosophy
therefore tends to present the beliefs that constitute this ‘philosophy’ as
things that do not change, that are somehow timeless. African traditional
systems of thought are therefore portrayed as placing minimal emphasis
upon rigorous argumentation and criticism in a search for truth that
provides for discarding the old and creating the new. Tradition somehow
becomes antithetical to innovation. Disputes between academic
ethnophilosophers thus arise primarily over how to arrive at a correct
interpretation of a static body of oral literature and oral traditions. (2010,
75-76)
Even with these challenges noted above, some African philosophers insist that,
“…ethnophilosophy is the only philosophy that an African of black extraction
can be proud of as it is rooted in African tradition and cultures” (MANGENA
2014, 96). With that said, we must ask at this point, what makes a discourse
philosophy? How do we measure to what degree a discourse qualifies as
philosophy? How is ethnophilosophy different from philosophy as we know it?
G. Bell notes that:
Hountondji’s fear was that ethnophilosophies dealt with African societies
“as a voiceless face under private observation, an object to be defined
and not the subject of a possible discourse,” i.e., not the subject of a two
way conversation. In either form of ethnophilosophy (universalistic or
pluralistic) was there a large amount of actual African philosophical
literature generated, that is, philosophy written by Africans—Alexis
Kagame’s work being one notable exception. (2002, 23-24)
Regardless of these challenges, Bodunrin appears to warn us not to jettison
ethnophilosophy because of the ready potentials it would offer in the coming
days. He notes:
The African Philosopher cannot deliberately ignore the study of the
traditional belief system of his people. Philosophical problems arise out
of real life situations. In Africa, more than in many other parts of the
modern world, traditional culture and beliefs still exercise a great
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
influence on the thinking and actions of men. At a time when many
people in the West believe that philosophy has become impoverished and
needs redirection, a philosophical study of traditional society may be the
answer. (1984, 13)
It was with an understanding of this caution and in the light of criticisms that
ethnophilosophy metamorphosed into systematic ethnophilosophy. D. A Masolo
was the first to use the expression, “Systematic Ethnophilosophy” to capture
Marcel Griaule’s essay on the Dogon people and his interview with Ogotemmeli
and all such attempts (1994, 68-83). In this work we use the expression
systematic ethnophilosophy rather differently. It refers to an individualistic,
critical, reflection articulated out intelligibly by an African who takes his
inspiration from cultural extracts or principles. It also differs from philosophic
sagacity in that it is not a search for sages and their interpretation of reality. The
individual African philosopher takes this principle, clause or idea from a
descriptive sense to a prescriptive level. The call for systematic ethnophilosophy
is a call for a critical, reflective and rational outlook on some cultural excavations
from African societies. It encourages the individuality of thoughts and the writing
of these thoughts. It is a rejection of a worldview driven ethnophilosophy to an
individual centred reflection of the philosophical essences of certain realities
using already existing cultural ideas that best express these thoughts.
It was the works and philosophies of those Odera Oruka refers to as
members of the ideological school that gave systematic ethnophilosophy a
bearing. It was a proportionate and passionate attempt to gather the remains of
Africa’s shattered persona by piecing together valuable cultural extracts.
Evidently, these were all reflected in the political thoughts of Nnamdi Azikwe,
Leopold Senghor, Julius Nyerere, Kwame Nkrumah, and Obafemi Awolowo. If
we insist that systematic African philosophy does not involve in any way
commentaries of cultural depth like those of Temples, Kagame and all such, then
critics may insist that we deny that there existed a philosophy in traditional
Africa. Since this is not so, systematic ethnophilosophy refers to certain cultural
excavations that serve as hypotheses for critical reflections by African scholars.
These extracts could be underling principles, clauses of contemporary social
relevance. In all, it suffices as non-cultural communally based commentary since
it is an individualistic, thought-driven and critical pursuit to interpret reality and
make intelligible input to the body of existing ideas.
Ethnophilosophy cannot be said to be systematic if it still discusses
subjects like Yoruba concept of Time, Akan concept of morality, Bantu concept
of being or force, Igbo concept of evil etc. Its concern must transcend cultural
world views or commentaries. This is in no way rejecting the idea of and
necessity of literature on such subjects. They are important subjects in the realms
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
of sociology, history, ethnography and perhaps anthropology but not philosophy.
On the other hand, (like what systematic ethnophilosophy advocates) a cultural
principle like say, “njikoka”, “ibuanyidanda” etc., which refers to the principles
of Ozumba’s integrativity and Asouzu’s complementarity respectively, can form
theoretical basis for a more critical pursuit to solving societal challenges or
addressing conceptual haziness. These principles could be likened to such
principles like utilitarianism, social justice, proportionate equality etc. With these
cultural extracts an African philosopher can find a suitable conceptual issue to
address on the impetus derived from this permutation.
“African” as a Color or Race
The failure to see Africa as a continent made up of many nations with distinct
cultural backgrounds, ideas and race but as the color “black” or as “Negros” is
not an uncommon phenomenon. The source of this, one may think is
etymological, but it is not so. Certain stereotypes over the years have categorized
all dark skinned people as Africans. The same challenge although slightly
different colored the conception of negritude and black consciousness. “The
assertion of black pride by members of the Negritude movement was attended by
a cry against assimilation. They felt that although it was theoretically based on a
belief in universal equality, it still assumed the superiority of European culture
and civilization over that of Africa” (Encyclopedia Britannica 2011, N. P). Thus
when the prefix African is mentioned reference is often made to the black or
Negro race. Maintaining this disposition is hurtful to the advancement of African
philosophy. Thus we must insist that African philosophy does not refer strictly to
pre-colonial philosophy done by people of “black extraction”(MANGENA 2014,
96) but philosophy done on the Continent of Africa, a reflection of African
existential realities and philosophy done by Africans. In this, we mean, a
philosophy that is philosophy in its content and authorship. More instructive for
us is the fact that:
… philosophy is not African on racial or linguistic lines but what makes
a philosophy African is the tradition of the philosophy: African cultural
experiences, history and tradition, with a grounding in an holistic
ontology, which is more of co-existence with nature, rather that conquest,
more of collectivism, rather that individualism, more of holism rather that
atomism or monism, more of sysnthesis rather than analysis. Authentic
African philosophy is that philosophy that is applied to the conceptual
problems of African life. (AZENABOR 2000, 326)
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
In this respect, it is of greater value to us to view the prefix African more as an a
object with several tentacles than to marginalise possible definitions. Therefore,
seeing the prefix “African” as a race excludes all northern African philosophers
from the matrix of African philosophy.
In Pursuit of a Unified Explanation for the Prefix “African” and Philosophy
in Africa
Philosophy is not the exclusive of any race and it is not a worldview. The
affirmative response in modern times is an advocacy for what Chimakonam calls
“systematic African philosophy” (2014, 12) and the denialist response to the
subject is an outright rejection of the universality of philosophy. As might have
been observed by attentive readers, the position of this work is that of the
affirmative. But more to this, the attempt at uncovering the possible implications
of the prefix “African” has been an eye opener.
Interpreting African philosophy through the lenses of the myth of
unanimity, negro race or ethnophilosophy will only give us a lopsided opinion on
what it means to have an African philosophy. It will be best appreciated in
modern times that the pursuit of a distinct quality that makes African philosophy
authentically African or what Sophie Oluwole refers to as the “Africanness” of a
philosophy (1991, 214) may be rather inconsequential. History has shown time
and time again that cultures evolve. Changes are often noted in cultures due to
interactions with other cultures and so the cycle continues. Culture then becomes
the sum total of mutually borrowed ideas and customs. It then will be utterly
incredulous to claim that there is a Western, American, Oriental or African
philosophy devoid of influence from the other. In the case of Africa, the
unfortunate event of colonialism has made it impossible for us to say the
continent or African philosophers are pure breed (uninfluenced) in the sense of
having a special “Africanity” (KANU 2012, 53) or Africanness. There may
however be certain elements that are still in their original form, they may be
elements in the past; they are what Jewsiewicki, Bogumil calls the “usable past”
(1989, 1).
A unified explanation of African philosophy will require that we first of
all rid ourselves from every form of ethnocentric commitment. When we begin to
lose touch of the general concern or subject matter of philosophy we begin to see
African philosophy as simply the exclusive of the African. Apparently, in
African universities we do Western philosophy. For us, what should qualify any
study for example as Western philosophy is its approach to explanation as well as
the works written by individual Western philosophers. Therefore, when I study
Plato, Descartes, and Hobbes I am doing Western philosophy. The same goes for
a European, if he reads the works of Asouzu on the ambivalence of human
interest and not necessarily on any subject matter related to African philosophy
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
per se he or she is doing African philosophy. Philosophy is universal. The laws of
logic, the burden of axiology, the questions of metaphysics, the problems of
socio-political philosophy and the concerns of epistemology all transcend
geographical boundaries. As Ezeani notes:
Philosophy is a transcendental human phenomenon. It is not restricted to
geography. European or African philosophy (localized philosophy) is a
reference to the products or thoughts of some individual critical thinkers
(philosophers) of that locality (e.g. Europe or Africa). Plato, for example,
is regarded as a philosopher and his dualism an element of Western
philosophy. But is the concept dualism (e.g. negative/positive,
male/female, body/spirit, black/white) not a universal philosophical
phenomenon? (2005, 18)
The diversion from traditional African thought must not be seen as an ill omen or
a gradual loss of identity. The unfortunate historical events of slavery and
colonialism have ensured that the African must necessarily contend with his new
personality. “There is an urgent need in Africa today for the kind of analysis that
would identify and separate the backward aspects of our culture from those
aspects that are worth keeping” (WIREDU 1984, 151). This is a call for what we
referred to as systematic ethnophilosophy where critical reflection is made on
cultural excavations such as Ibuanyidanda philosophy of Asouzu, Njikoka
philosophy of Ozumba and later Chimakonam, Uwa Ontology of Iroegbu etc. An
appropriate disposition must be maintained if we must be successful in our task.
Asouzub captures this when he states:
Progress and stagnation of African philosophy depends largely on the attitude of
Africans themselves who have the primary duty to patronize and promote it. In our
institution of higher learning, a conducive atmosphere has to be created for the
promotion and patronage of ideas, systems and methods of African philosophers
in view of promoting African philosophy. That is to say, the thoughts of regional
philosophers should be studied and made available to students and should be
brought to compete with each other. (2007, 300)
Thus from a unified explanation, philosophy in Africa must not be seen as
regionalized philosophy but rather a contribution to the subject matter and quest
of philosophy—the search for truth.
Conclusion
In conclusion we have succinctly addressed the following; (i) The prefix African
(ii) Philosophy in Africa and African Philosophy (iii) Implications of the Prefix
“African” for Philosophy in Africa to include the myth of unanimity, Africa as a
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
color and ethnophilosophy (iv) Understanding the Prefix “African” and
Philosophy in Africa from a unified explanation; insisting that we must not
separate philosophy into geographical enclaves, for just as the subject matters of
the physical sciences are distinct and clear and transcend geographical
boundaries, philosophy possesses certain qualities that enable easy identification
regardless of the shades it comes in (music, literature, folklores, stories etc.).Thus
Asouzuc notes:
In the case of philosophy, it is in view of this unity, guaranteed by a
unified subject matter, that philosophy, as a discipline is sustained. In the
absence of a unified subject matter, as this is a general practice in the
other sciences, and which serves as a credible guide in matters of
validation of our claims about the world, it becomes difficult, even today,
for philosophers to speak with harmonized mind, as scientists in a way
that transcends geographical and ideological boundaries. (2007, 100)
In sum, our emphasis is to speak of African philosophy in the sense we speak of
Western or other world philosophies. This identification and interpretation we
believe will help the growth and progress of philosophy in Africa.
Relevant Literature
1. "Africa". [Encyclopædia Britannica Deluxe Edition], NP, 2011.
Encyclopædia Britannica: Chicago. E-book.
2. ASIRA, Asira. “What is African Philosophy?”, [Philosophy and
Logic Today, INNOCENT Asouzu Ed.], pp196-207, 2004.
University of Calabar Press: Calabar. Paperback.
3. ASOUZU, Innocenta. [The Method and Principles of
Complementary Reflection in and Beyond African Philosophy],
2004. University of Calabar Press: Calabar. Paperback.
4. _____b. [Ibuaru, The Heavy Burden of Philosophy beyond African
Philosophy], 2007. Lit Verlag: Zurich. Paperback.
5. _____c.. [Ibuanyidanda New Complementary Ontology], 2007. Lit
Verlag: Zurich. Paperback.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
6. ASUKWO, Offiong. “The Problem of Language in African
Philosophy”, [Footmarks to Landmarks on African philosophy
UDUIGWOMEN A.F Ed.], pp30-35, 2009. Obaroh & Ogbinaka
Publishers: Lagos. Paperback.
7. AZENABOR, Godwin. “The Idea of African Philosophy in
African Language” [Indian Philosophical Quarterly], pp321-328,
July, 2000. Vol XXVII. No 3. E-book.
8. BODUNRIN, Peter. “The question of African Philosophy”,
[African Philosophy an Introduction, WRIGHT, Richard Ed.],
pp1-23, 1984. University Press of America: Lanham. Paperback.
9. CHIMAKONAM, Jonathana. “Why can’t there be an African
Logic?”, [Integrative Humanism Journal], pp141-152, September,
2011. Vol 1. No 2. Paperback.
10. ______b. “Dating and Periodization Question in African
Philosophy”, [Atuolu Omalu: Some Unanswered Questions in
Contemporary African Philosophy, CHIMAKONAM, Jonathan
Ed.), pp9-34, 2014. University Press of America: New York.
Paperback.
11. EGBEKE, Aja. “African Philosophy: Conceptions and Problem”,
[Nsukka Journal of the Humanities], pp92-102, 1999. No 10.
Ebook.
12. EZEANI, Emefiena. [Philosophy as Intelligent and Pragmatic
Questioning], 2005. Veritas Lumen Publishers: London.
Paperback.
13. HALLEN, Barry. “Ethnophilosophy Redefined?”, [Thought and
Practice: A Journal of the Philosophical Association of Kenya
New Series], June 2010. Vol 2. No 1. Paperback.
14. HOUNTONDJI, Paulin. [African Philosophy Myth and Reality],
1983. Indiana University Press: Bloomington. Paperback.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
15. JEWSIEWICKI, Bogumil. “African Historical Studies: Academic
Knowledge as ‘Usable Past’ and Radical Scholarship”. [The
African Studies Review], pp1-76, 1989. Vol 32. No 3. Web.
16. KANU, I. Anthony. “The Africanity and Philosophicality of
African Philosophy”, [Internet Afrrev: An International Online
Multi-disciplinary Journal], pp52-54, 2012. Vol 1. No 2. Ebook.
17. MAKINDE, Akin. “Philosophy in Africa”, [The Substance of
African Philosophy, MOMOH, C. S. Ed.], 2000. African
Philosophy Projects’ Publications: Auchi. Paperback.
18. MANGENA, Fainos. “In Defence of Ethno-philosophy: A Brief
Response to Kanu’s Eclecticism”, [Filosofia Theoretica: Journal
of African Philosophy, Culture and Religion], pp96-107, January
June 2014. Vol 3. No 1. Paperback.
19. MASOLO, D.A. [African Philosophy in Search of Identity], 1994.
Indiana University Press: Bloomington, Indiana. Paperback.
20. MEREDITH, Martin. [The State of Africa, A History of Fifty
Years of Independence], 2005. Free Press: London. Paperback.
21. MESEMBE, Edet. “Metaphysics, Contemporary African
Philosophy and Ethnocentric Commitment”, [Interactions in the
History of Philosophy. PHILHIST’13 Conference Proceedings,
EFE Duyan, AYSE Güngör Ed.], No 778, 2013. Mimar Sinan
Fine Arts University: Turkey. Paperback.
22. "Negritude." [Encyclopædia Britannica Deluxe Edition], N. P,
2011. Encyclopædia Britannica: Chicago. E-book.
23. NZE, C. “African Philosophy: Okolo’s Interpretation”, [Okolo on
African Philosophy and African Theology], 1990. Cecta Nigeria
Ltd: Enugu. Paperback.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
24. OYESHILE, Olatunji, “On Defining African Philosophy: History,
Challenges and Perspectives,” [Humanity & Social Sciences
Journal], pp57-64, 2008. Vol 3. No 1. Ebook.
25. OZUMBA, Godfrey and CHIMAKONAM Jonathan. [Njikoka
Amaka Further Discussions on the Philosophy of Integrative
Humanism], 2014. Series Vol 2. Third Logic Option: Calabar.
Paperback.
26. RICHARD, Bell. [Understanding African Philosophy A Cross
Cultural Approach to Classical and Contemporary Issues], 2002.
Routledge: New York. Paperback.
27. SOGOLO, Godwin. [Foundations of African philosophy], 1993.
Ibadan University Press: Ibadan. Paperback.
28. TEMPELS, Placide. [Bantu Philosophy], 1959. Présence
Africaine: Paris. Ebook.
29. UDUIGWOMEN, Andrew. “Philosophy and the Place of African
Philosophy”, [Footmarks to Landmarks on African philosophy
UDUIGWOMEN A.F Ed.], pp30-35, 2009. Obaroh & Ogbinaka
Publishers: Lagos. Paperback.
30. UDUMA, Uduma. “The Question of the “African” in African
Philosophy: In Search of a Criterion for the Africanness of a
Philosophy”, [Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy,
Culture and Religions], pp127-146, January-June 2014. Vol 3. No
1. Paperback.
31. WIREDU, Kwasia. “The Concept of Truth in the Akan
Language”, [Philosophy in Africa, Trends and Perspectives
BODUNRIN, Peter Ed.], pp43-67, 1985. University of Ile-Ife
Press: Ile-Ife. Paperback.
32. ______b. “How not to compare African Thought with Western
Thought”, [African Philosophy an Introduction, WRIGHT,
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
Richard Ed.], pp149-162, 1984. University Press of America:
Lanham. Paperback.
33. WRIGHT, Richard. “Investigating African Philosophy”, [African
Philosophy an Introduction, Richard Wright Ed.], pp41-55, 1984.
University Press of America: Lanham, New York. Paperback.
Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and Religions
CAN AFRICANA WOMEN TRULY EMBRACE ECOLOGICAL
FEMINISM?
Fainos MANGENA, PhD
Prof. of Philosophy
Department of Religious Studies, Classics and Philosophy, University of
Zimbabwe
Abstract
My starting point in this essay is that, if it can be ascertained that there is
something called Black African feminism (which represents the interests of some
Black African women) as claimed by feminists and other like-minded African
women, then the existence of Black African ecological feminism should be a
matter of deduction. In this essay, I interrogate this position using Karen
Warren’s version of ecological feminism which holds that there are important
historical and conceptual connections between the domination of women in
society and the domination of nature. This interrogation also prompts me to trace
the history of traditional feminism with a view to showing that while, in the
West, there could be important connections – historical, symbolic and theoretical – between the oppression of women and the cruel treatment of nature, the same
cannot be said of Africa, especially sub-Saharan Africa where nature is owned or
guarded by the spirit world. Using the Africana womanist perspective and the
deductive method in philosophy, I argue that traditional feminism together with
Warren’s ecological feminism completely ignore the experiences and aspirations
of Black African women, thereby ruling out the possibility of the existence – in
the truest sense – of both Black African feminism and Black African ecological
feminism.
Keywords: Ecological feminism, Feminism, Oppression, Patriarchal Conceptual
Framework,
Deductive Logic, Validity, Africana Womanism
Introduction
There are different forms of ecological feminism with all of them agreeing that
there are important connections between the oppression of women and the ill
treatment of non-human animals by humans. My task in this essay is to reflect on
Warren’s defense of ecological feminism as contained in her classic essay
entitled: “The Power and Promise of Ecological Feminism” with a view to
establishing whether this theory is transferrable to sub-Saharan Africa. In this
essay, Warren begins by making the observation that there are important
connections between the domination of women and the domination of nature.
Warren links this connection with what she calls the Oppressive Patriarchal
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
Conceptual Framework which, according to her, looks down upon women the
same way it looks down upon non-human creatures. Using the Africana
Womanist theory conceptualized by Clenora Hudson-Weems and the method of
deduction in philosophy, I argue that while the discourse on feminism has
received world wide acclaim and while feminists have raised genuine concerns
about how they are oppressed by their male counterparts, I find it difficult to
apply or transpose the idea of feminism, let alone ecological feminism to Africa
since the history of feminism, and by extension ecological feminism precludes
the values and experiences of women of African descent. As a result of this
charge and given the spiritual character of African environments, I argue that
there is no correlation between the oppression of women and the ill-treatment of
nature in Africa. In the final analysis, this reasoning automatically allows me to
draw the conclusion that: “No Black African women are ecological feminists.”
Below, I outline and explain the deductive method in philosophy which I use
partly to dismiss both African feminism and the idea of African ecological
feminism.
The Deductive Method in Philosophy
The deductive method in Philosophy stipulates that the conclusion of an
argument must necessarily follow from its premises (COPI 1994, 54). Thus,
when the reasoning in a deductive argument is correct, that argument becomes
valid; when the reasoning in a deductive argument is incorrect, that argument
becomes invalid (1994, 56). In every deductive argument, either the premises
succeed in providing conclusive grounds for the truth of the conclusion, or they
do not succeed. If they do, the argument becomes valid and sound. If they don’t,
the argument may remain valid but unsound. So, validity has to do with the
formal or syntactic relational aspect of the premises and conclusion in an
argument, while soundness has to do with the semantic aspect of the premises
and conclusion in an argument. But in all cases, validity is a pre-condition for
soundness, that is to say, an argument cannot be sound without being valid.
The three examples below show how valid and sound arguments are
structured, with argument A representing a valid argument and argument B and
C representing sound arguments:
A
B
1. All Black African feminists are unmarried Women
2. All unmarried women are Ecological feminists
Therefore, all Ecological feminists are Black African feminists
1. All Feminists are White supremacists
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
2. No White supremacists are Black African women
Therefore, No Black African women are feminists
Note that if we take the conclusion of argument B above to be the premise of
argument C, below, we can draw the conclusion: “No Black African women are
Ecological feminists” as illustrated by argument C below:
C
1.
No Black African women are feminists
Therefore, No Black African women are Ecological feminists
Notice that the conclusion of argument A, “All ecological feminists are Black
African women,” follows from premises 1 and 2. This makes the argument valid.
But in deductive inferences, validity does not always translate to soundness or
truthfulness. Thus, while argument A is valid, it is not sound because it is not
true that “All Black African feminists are unmarried women,” or that “All
unmarried women are ecological feminists.” The conclusion drawn from these
two premises is also not true, that is, “All ecological feminists are Black African
women.” Having said this, it is important to note that argument B is valid and
sound in the following ways: In my view and judging from the nature and
character of feminism which I shall outline later in this essay, it is true that “All
feminists are White supremacists.” It is also true that “No Black African women
are White supremacists.” The conclusion – “No Black African women are
feminists” – which is drawn from two premises above is also true in my view.
I also take argument C, which is a development of argument B to be an
example of a valid and sound argument. In my view, if the premise “No Black
African women are feminists” is based on a truism, then the conclusion “No
Black African women are ecological feminists” should immediately follow. Note
that arguments A and B are mediate inferences as the conclusion is drawn from
two premises but argument C is an immediate inference as the conclusion is
drawn from one premise. In the rest of the essay, I outline and explain the
premises that lead to the conclusion that “No Black African women are
feminists” and “No Black African women are ecological feminists” as
represented by arguments B and C. To kick start this important debate, I now
present Warren’s ecological feminism.
Warren’s presentation of Ecological Feminism
According to Warren, ecological feminism is the position that there are important
connections—historical, symbolic and theoretical—between the domination of
women and the domination of nature (WARREN 1990, 342). Warren argues that
because the conceptual connections between the dual dominations of women and
nature are located in an Oppressive Patriarchal Conceptual Framework
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
characterized by the logic of domination, (1) traditional feminism must expand
feminism to include ecological feminism (2) ecological feminism must provide a
framework for developing a distinctively feminist environmental ethic (1990,
342).
But how are these Oppressive Patriarchal Conceptual Frameworks to be
explained by ecological feminists? Warren begins by defining and explaining
Conceptual frameworks in general before defining and explaining Oppressive
Patriarchal Conceptual Frameworks. For Warren, a Conceptual Framework is a
set of basic beliefs, values, attitudes and assumptions which shape and reflect
how one views oneself and one’s own world (1990, 342). It is a socially
constructed lens through which we perceive ourselves and others. It is affected
by such factors as gender, race, class, age, nationality and religious background
(1990, 342). Lynn White observes that:
What people do about their ecology depends on what they think about
themselves in relation to things around them. Human ecology is deeply
conditioned by beliefs about our nature and destiny – that is, by
religion. (WHITE 1967, Web. N. P.)
The above position by White, sets us right into the philosophical discourse of
Oppressive Conceptual Frameworks which Warren defines as frameworks that
explain, justify and maintain relationships of domination and subordination
(WARREN 1990, 342). When an Oppressive Conceptual Framework is
patriarchal, it explains, justifies and maintains the subordination of women by
men (1990, 342).
For Warren, there are three significant features of Oppressive
Patriarchal Conceptual Frameworks, namely: 1. Value-hierarchical thinking,
which is a kind of thinking that places higher value, status or prestige on what is
“up” rather than on what is “down.” 2. Value dualisms, that is, disjunctive pairs
in which the disjuncts are seen as oppositional (rather than as complementary)
and exclusive (rather than as inclusive) and which place higher value or status to
that which has historically been identified as “mind,” “reason” and “male” than
to that which has historically been identified as “body,” “emotion” and “female.”
3. The logic of domination, that is, a structure of argumentation which leads to a
justification of subordination (1990, 342).
For Warren, this third feature of Oppressive Patriarchal Conceptual
Frameworks is the most significant. The logic of domination is not just a logical
structure. It also involves a substantive value system, since an ethical premise is
needed to permit or sanction the “just” subordination of that which is
subordinate (1990, 342). This justification typically is given on grounds of some
alleged characteristic (for example, rationality) which the dominant (for
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
example, men) have and the subordinate (for example, women) lack (1990, 342).
Warren argues that contrary to what many feminists and eco-feminists have said
or suggested, there may be nothing inherently problematic about “hierarchal
thinking” or even “value-hierarchical thinking” in contexts other than contexts
of oppression (1990, 342).
Warren argues that hierarchal thinking is important in daily living for
classifying data, comparing information and organizing material (1990, 342).
Even “value-hierarchical thinking” can be quite acceptable in certain contexts.
For Warren, the problem is not simply that value-hierarchal thinking and value
dualisms are used, but the way in which each has been used in Oppressive
Conceptual Frameworks to establish inferiority and justify subordination (1990,
342). It is the logic of domination coupled with value hierarchal thinking and
value dualisms, which justify subordination (1990, 342).
For Warren, what is explanatorily basic, then, about the nature of
Oppressive Conceptual Frameworks is the logic of domination and that the logic
of domination is explanatorily basic is important for at least three reasons: First,
without the logic of domination, a description of similarities and differences
would be just that – a description of similarities and differences (1990, 342).
Consider the claim, “Humans are different from rocks in that humans can
radically and consciously re-shape the communities in which they live; humans
are similar to plants and rocks in that they are both members of the ecological
community” (1990, 342).
Even if humans are better than plants and rocks with respect to the
conscious ability of humans to radically transform communities, one does not
thereby get any morally relevant distinction between humans and non-humans,
or an argument for the dominance of plants and rocks by humans (1990, 342).
To get these conclusions, one need to add at least two powerful assumptions;
namely, (A2) and (A4) in argument A below:
(A1) Humans do, and plants and rocks do not, have the capacity
to consciously and radically change the community in which
they live.
(A2) Whatever has the capacity to consciously and radically
change the community in which it lives is morally superior to
whatever lacks this capacity.
(A3) Thus, humans are morally superior to plants and rocks
(A4) For any X and Y, if X is morally superior to Y, then X is
morally justified in subordinating Y.
(A5) Thus, humans are morally justified in subordinating plants
and rocks (1990, 342).
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
Without the two assumptions that humans are morally superior to (at
least some) non-humans, (A2), and that superiority justifies
subordination, (A4), all one has is some difference between humans and
some non-humans (1990, 342). This is true even if that difference is
given in terms of superiority. Thus, it is the logic of domination, (A4),
which is the bottom line in ecological feminist discussions of oppression
(1990, 342).
Second, ecological feminists argue that, at least in Western
societies, the Oppressive Conceptual Framework which sanctions the
twin dominations of women and nature is patriarchal, one characterized
by all three features of an Oppressive Conceptual Framework (1990,
342). Many ecological feminists claim that, historically, within at least
the dominant Western culture, a patriarchal framework has sanctioned
the following argument:
(B1) Women are identified with nature and the realm of the physical;
men are identified with the “human” and the realm of the mental.
(B2) Whatever is identified with nature and the realm of the physical is
inferior to (below) whatever is identified with the human and the realm
of the mental; or, conversely, the latter is superior (above) to the former.
(B3) Thus, women are inferior to (below) men; or, conversely, men are
superior to (above) women.
(B4) For any X and Y, if X is superior to Y, then X is justified in
subordinating Y.
(B5) Thus, men are justified in subordinating women (1990, 342).
Having outlined and explained Warren’s ecological feminism, I now try
to establish and explain the premises that will lead to the conclusions that
“No Black African women are feminists” and “No Black African
Women are Ecological feminists.” I do this in two ways: First, I trace the
history of feminism with a view to establish whether or not Africana
women are part of the project of feminism, and second, I then try to find
out if the idea of ecological feminism is all encompassing, that is, is it
cross-cultural to the effect that it can also address the concerns of
Africana women?
A Brief History of Feminism
The true history of feminism, its origin and participants reveal its blatant racist
background, thereby establishing its incompatibility with Africana women (that
is, continental African women and those in the Diaspora) (WEEMS 1993, 18).
Feminism, earlier called the Woman’s Suffrage Movement (WSM), started when
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
a group of liberal white women, whose concerns then were for the abolition of
slavery and equal rights for all people regardless of race, class and sex,
dominated the scene on the national level during the early to middle century
(1993, 18). At the time of the civil war in America, such leaders as Susan B.
Anthony and Elizabeth Cady Stanton held the universalist philosophy on the
natural rights of women (both white and black) to full citizenship, which
included the right to vote.
However, in 1870, the fifteenth Amendment to the constitution of the
United States of America ratified the voting rights of African men leaving
women, White women, in particular and their desire for the same rights
unaddressed (1993, 342). Middle class White women were naturally
disappointed, for they had assumed that their efforts toward securing full
citizenship for Africana people would ultimately benefit them, too, in their desire
for full citizenship, as voting citizens (1993, 18). The result was a racist reaction
to the amendment and to Africans in particular (1993, 18). In 1890, the National
American Woman Suffrage Association (NAWSA) was founded by northern
White women…epitomizing the growing race chauvinism of the late nineteenth
century (1993, 18).
The organization, which brought together the National Woman Suffrage
Association (NWSA) and the American Woman Suffrage Association (AWSA)
departed from Susan B Anthony’s original women suffrage posture (1993, 18).
They asserted that the vote for women should be utilized chiefly by middle class
White women, who could aid their husbands in preserving the virtues of the
Republic from the threat of unqualified and biological inferiors (Africana men)
who with the power of the vote, could gain a political foothold in the American
system (1993, 18). This is how feminism was born.
Note of course, that Africana women were not even part of the equation
and never became part of the equation in the minds of these White women. This
raises a lot of eye brows for those Africana women who, today, claim to be
feminists. They face hard questions such as: On what basis do they justify
feminism? How can they claim to own an idea that is foreign to them? Aren’t
they championing the White women’s interests? These hard questions and many
others only help to complicate the puzzle for Africana women who claim to be
feminists when in actual fact feminism excluded them right from the onset.
Critical Remarks
Having looked at this brief history of feminism, it is important to answer two
critical questions: What is feminism? Who is a feminist? To begin with,
feminism, a term conceptualized and adopted by White women involves an
agenda that was designed to meet the needs and demands of that particular group
(1993, 19). For this reason, it is quite plausible for white women to identify with
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
feminism and the feminist movement (1993, 18). Although this definition of
feminism automatically excludes Black African women or Africana women, later
on feminism expanded to include White men who were also interested in seeing
women being treated equally.
In fact, elsewhere I argue that the emphasis on feminists as male or
female is important because it is wrong to assume that only white women can be
feminists since being a feminist or a non-feminist is not a biological construct but
a way in which one look at life (MANGENA 2011, 118). The emergency of
homosexual practices in the West also meant that those men who assumed the
role of “wives” also had to identify with feminism and to fight for the liberation
of women from the yoke of patriarchy. So, in proper terminology, a feminist is
someone [male or female] who believes that men and women are inherently
equal in all respects relevant to how they should be treated (BARCALOW 1994,
95).
Judging from the way the history of feminism is presented above, it is
probably clear that in her definition of feminism, Barcalow fell short of saying
that a feminist was someone [white male or female] who believes that White men
and women were inherently equal in all respects relevant to how they should be
treated. If feminism is a Western concept as demonstrated above, then why are
there designations such as Black feminism or African feminism? Don’t they point
or attest to the fact that feminism can be cross-cultural?
In my response to the questions above, I argue that those women who
have adopted feminism and named it either Black feminism or African feminism
either do not know the history of feminism or ignore this history to deliberately
mislead other Africana women for selfish reasons. This is so because the
objectives of, for instance, Black Feminism are not any different from those of
traditional feminism. In fact, Black feminism is simply an imitation of traditional
feminism. Weems (1993, 35) captures this point succinctly when she says:
Black feminism is some Africana women’s futile attempt to fit into the
constructs of an established White female paradigm. At best, Black
feminism may relate to sexual discrimination outside of the Africana
community, but cannot claim to resolve the critical problems within it
which are influenced by racism and classism.
Despite variations in the source of their daily struggles (That is, Black/African or
White Women), they both blame patriarchy for their inferior positions in society.
For instance, while feminists in the West have focused on issues of reproduction
and sexuality; the so-called African feminists have attached importance to
heterosexuality, issues of motherhood as well as bread and butter issues, culture
and power (1993, 38). However, both feminists in the West and the so-called
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
African feminists blame patriarchy for marginalizing them. But what is more
worrying is that African feminists do not have a thorough-bred African theory to
justify their claims. Instead, they use Western feminism as their template as well
and they justify this use by arguing that feminism can be re-defined to suit the
needs of Africana women.
My challenge with this thinking is that, it gives the impression that
Africana people cannot invent and defend anything of their own but they can
only discover and modify other people’s ideas or theories. This is fortunately not
true as Africana people are capable of inventing and defending their own ideas or
theories. For instance, Africanas have successfully invented and defended the
theory of hunhu, ubuntu or botho (as is the case with Southern Africa), omundu
(as is the case with some countries in East Africa), Umunna and Okra (as is the
case with some countries in West Africa, for instance, Nigeria and Ghana
respectively) and Ma’at (as is the case with some countries in North Africa, for
example, Egypt). These are theories that define Africa’s ethical, metaphysical
and epistemological thought. The theories attach importance to the value of
group belonging and collective responsibility sub-summed under communalism.
The theory proceeds by noting that the importance or value of any person can
only be expressed through that person’s contribution to the betterment of the
group. A hunhu or ubuntu theory says, munhu munhu muvanhu or umuntu
ngumuntu ngabantu (a person is a person through other persons). A hunhu or
ubuntu theory does not create gender binaries as is the case with feminism which
divides people based on biology and sexuality. It prefers to focus on roles and
responsibilities of men and women which roles point to the fact that men and
women work together for the betterment of their communities. Thus, hunhu or
ubuntu is a world view…and a way of life for the African (MANGENA 2012,
11).
It is from such African moral theories as hunhu or ubuntu that Africana
women like Weems have successfully invented and defended Africana
womanism in the face of stiff resistance from the so-called Black feminists or
African feminists whose main agenda is Western. By definition, Africana
womanism is an ideology created and designed for all women of Africana descent
and it is grounded in African culture, and therefore, it necessarily focuses on the
unique experiences, struggles, needs and desires of African women (WEEMS
1993, 22). As Weems maintains, Africana womanism sits well with the cultures
of sub-Saharan Africa because of its emphasis on the centrality of self-definition,
self-naming and the place of the family or community (1993: 22). Weems
remarks, thus:
Africana womanism emerged from the acknowledgement of a long
standing authentic agenda for that group of women of African descent
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
who needed only to be properly named and officially defined according
to their own unique historical and cultural matrix, one that would
reflect the co-existence of a man and a woman in a concerted struggle
for the survival of their entire family/community. (WEEMS 2007, 289)
The above paragraph shows that Africana womanism puts the interests of men
and women, their families or communities ahead of the interests of individual
men and individual women as is the case with feminism, including ecological
feminism. Thus, any Africana woman who embraces feminism is most likely to
be isolated by her peers at one end and vilified by those people whose ideas or
theories she wants to embrace at the other end.
So, the problem with discovering and modifying theories and concepts
like feminism to suit particular cultures like those of Africa are that an African
(man or woman) cannot wholly own such theories and concepts making it
difficult for him or her to fully identify with the theory. In most cases, the one
who discovers the theory or idea cannot claim to belong to the inner circle of
those who invented it— he or she remains cast as the other. It is like somebody
who gatecrashes a wedding party and suddenly wants to control the wedding
proceedings or wants to sit at the high table with the newly-weds.
The point I am putting across is that as a result of colonialism, some
Africana women adopted the feminist discourse by white colonialists while
others did not. Those who adopted feminism are the ones who today call
themselves Black or African feminists and those who declined to associate
themselves with feminism are today called Africana womanists. The latter
decided to define their experiences and challenges in the context of their
experiences, traditions and cultures. In other words, they did not look elsewhere
for answers to their challenges. To this end, Weems (1993, 34) notes, thus:
Too many Blacks have taken the theoretical framework of “feminism”
and have tried to make it fit their particular circumstances. Rather than
create their own paradigm and name and define themselves, some
Africana women, scholars in particular, have been persuaded by white
feminists to adopt or adapt to the White concept and terminology of
feminism. The real benefit of the amalgamation of Black feminism and
White feminism goes to White feminists who can increase their power
base by expanding their scope with the convenient consensus that
sexism is their commonality and primary concern.
Patricia Hill Collins (1996, 11) highlights what she considers to be drawbacks to
buying into a feminist ideology that is outside of one’s culture (1996, 11). First,
she points out that gender works with racism to maintain oppression (1996, 11).
Second, she argues that an acceptance of feminism by Africana women translates
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
into the rejection of Africana men, given the theoretical underpinnings of the
movement (1996, 12). Remember at its formative stages, feminism was meant to
challenge the American constitution which had given Africana men voting rights
ahead of White women.
Any attempt by women of Africana descent to accept feminism leaving
men alone to fight against racism and classicism will leave men vulnerable.
Third, feminism is based on individualism rather than communalism and yet
Africans are communal by orientation. Besides, communalism is a life style and
value more akin to African Americans and continental Africans and their
ancestry than individualism (1996, 12). As I mentioned earlier, this lifestyle and
value is sub-summed under hunhu or ubuntu or botho (in Southern Africa),
omundu (in some parts of East Africa), ma’at (in Egypt) and Okra (in Ghana)
among others.
Those Africana women who have embraced feminism have done so for
two reasons, (1) feminism’s theoretical and methodological legitimacy in the
academy and their desire to remain a legitimate part of the academic community,
and (2) the absence of a suitable framework for their individual needs as Africana
women (WEEMS 1993, 16). Collins (1996, 16) thinks that feminism cannot be a
viable methodology for Black women. In particular, she challenges the
acceptance of the concept of feminism ipso facto by Black women arguing that
some of the characteristics of feminism are in conflict with the moral ethos of an
oppressed people whose past is marred by the collective actions of the oppressor
group (COLLINS 1996, 16).
In her full scale attack on feminism and by extension, African feminism;
Filomina Chioma Steady argues that the designation African feminism is
problematic as it naturally suggests an alignment with feminism, a concept that
has been alien to the plight of Africana women from its inception (STEADY
cited in WEEMS 1993, 17). This is particularly the case in reference to racism
and classicism which are prevailing obstacles in the lives of Africana people.
Steady puts it thus:
Regardless of one’s position, the implications of the feminist
movement for the black woman are complex… Several factors set the
black woman apart as having a different order of priorities. She is
oppressed not simply because of her sex but ostensibly because of her
race, and for the majority, essentially because of their class. Women
belong to different socio-economic groups and do not represent a
universal category. Because the majority of black women are poor,
there is likely to be some alienation from the middle class aspect of the
women’s movement which perceives feminism as an attack on men
rather than on a system which thrives on inequality. (1993, 17)
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
What I can discern from the above paragraph by Steady is that by virtue of
having a different order of priorities compared to those of White women, black
women cannot be feminists. For instance, Black women are still fighting poverty,
race and class and this is different from White women who overcame these evils
a long time ago. Hence, feminism and more specifically, Black feminism or
African feminism is extremely problematic as labels for the true Africana woman
(WEEMS 1993, 16).
Is Ecological Feminism applicable in Africa, and among Africana women in
the Diaspora?
To begin with, the history of feminism as presented above seems to show no
connections between the oppression of women of Africana descent and the ill
treatment of nature. This is so because this history does not recognize the
existence and contribution of Africana women in the feminist discourse in the
first place. As noted above, feminism as a political movement that was meant to
address the concerns of White women whose rights to vote were not respected.
Later on, it spread to other spheres of life but its main thrust was to advance the
interests of the White women. Thus, it was and still remains a project by and for
White women even today. If this history is anything to go by, then it follows that
ecological feminism is also a White women’s project, for the simple reason that it
is a type of feminism that seeks to link the oppression of women with the ill
treatment of nature.
While many academics uncritically adopt feminism, most Africana
women, in general do not identify with the concept in its entirety and thus cannot
see themselves as feminists (1993, 15). This also means that the conceptual
connections between the dual dominations of women and nature as put by
Warren are only cultural and not cross-cultural. That is, they only apply to
Warren’s context and not the context of Africa. For instance, traditional
feminism cannot expand to include ecological feminism in sub-Saharan Africa
since feminism by its nature is only a White women’s project restricted to
Western cultures. On the basis of this critique, a conclusion can be drawn from
this premise that –No Black African women are Ecological feminists.
It is also not possible for ecological feminism to develop a distinctively
feminist environmental ethic that can be applied across cultures given that most
Africans do not identify with the concept of feminism because of its history and
scope. In fact, most Africana women identify with Womanism and not
Feminism. By extension, this also means that Africana women cannot identify
with ecological feminism. It was easier for White women like Warren to coin the
phrase Ecological feminism but this cannot be applied to sub-Saharan Africa in
the sense that the genesis of the word “womanism” shows that there is no
correlation between women’s oppression at the hands of men and the ill
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
treatment of nature. In her definition of womanism, Weems (1993, 21) observes
that:
The term “woman,” and by extension “womanism,” is far more
appropriate than female (“feminism”) because of one major
distinction—only a female of the human race can be a woman.
“Female,” on the other hand, can refer to a member of the animal or
plant kingdom as well as to a member of the human race.
As the above paragraph shows, it is easier for feminists to talk of ecological
feminism, than it is for Africana womanists to talk about the same without
distorting African social and environmental realities and experiences given—as
shown above—that the word “feminist” comes from the word “female” which
applies to both human beings and animals or plants and yet as Weems put it
above, womanism refers only to a female of the human race. Thinkers like
White also believe that although the idea of conceptual frameworks cannot be
ruled out in Western Europe, the only link or connection that exists is that
between men and nature.
For White, this relationship is brought to bear by the advent of Science
and Technology. Science and Technology—hitherto quite separate activities,
joined to give mankind powers which, to judge by many of the ecologic effects,
are out of control (WHITE 1967, Web. N. P.). This led men to conclude that
they were superior to nature, contemptuous of it, willing to use it to their
slightest whim (WHITE 1967, Web. N. P.). No attempt is made to look at the
connection between men and women. This also means that Warren’s idea of
Oppressive Conceptual Frameworks when pitched against this position is found
wanting. Warren’s Oppressive Conceptual Frameworks are also found wanting
in that they are out of sync with African social and environmental realities.
In sub-Saharan Africa, the environment is owned by the ancestral
spirits. In Shona culture, in particular, these ancestral spirits are referred to as
varidzi ve masango (custodians of the environment and its content). This means
that human beings (men and women) have no control over the behavior of the
environment to warrant a comparison between the oppression of women and
the ill-treatment of the environment. It is also critical to note that in sub
Saharan Africa, men and women are victims of racism and classicism which
means that there is no such thing as value-hierarchical thinking as men do not
look at themselves as being of higher status or prestige than women. They
consider women to be their equal partners in their fight against racism and
classicism. Against this background, Joyce Ladner (cited in WEEMS 1993, 21)
notes that “Black women do not perceive their enemy to be black men, but
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
rather the enemy is considered to be oppressive forces in the larger society
which subjugate black men, women and children”.
The above arguments do not only eliminate value hierarchal thinking but
the other two features of Oppressive Conceptual Frameworks as well, that is,
value dualisms and the logic of domination which divides people based on both
socially constructed characteristics and biological characteristics such as “reason
and emotion” as well as “male and female” respectively. I argue that in sub
Saharan Africa such binaries do not exist as the emphasis is not on whether men
are more rational than women or women are more emotional than men as is the
case with Warren’s value dualisms and the logic of domination.
The emphasis is on how intellectual assets like “reason” and “emotion”
can be used for the betterment of the community. These assets appeal at the
community level than at individual level. Hence, we talk of communal/group
rationality rather than individual rationality (MANGENA 2012, 10). In this kind
of set up no one [male or female] can dominate the other. In fact, a man (the male
category) can play the role of a mother to his sister’s children in the event that the
biological mother is dead or absent and all mothers are women (the female
category).
Conversely, a woman (the female category) can play the role of a father
to her brother’s children in the event that the biological father has passed on and
fathers are men (the male category) (MANGENA and MUHWATI 2013) What
does this mean logically speaking? It probably means that if the argument I am
presenting is pointing to the fact that feminism is out of sync with African
realities/experiences, it follows necessarily that ecological feminism which is
best explained by the three features of Oppressive Conceptual Frameworks
discussed above is also out of sync with African realities/ experiences. Thus, the
conclusion—No Black African women are ecological feminists—would follow
with necessity.
Conclusion
This essay was an attempt to establish whether or not a conclusion can be drawn
to the effect that there is something called African ecological feminism. The
essay progressed through the use of Africana womanism as a theory and the
deductive method in philosophy to draw its warranted conclusions. The argument
was put thus, if it can be ascertained that there is something called Black or
African feminism, then that there is African ecological feminism should be a
matter of deduction. The essay began by presenting Warren’s ecological
feminism before looking at the history of feminism and showing that this history
precludes the values, experiences and aspirations of Africana women. By
deduction, this automatically meant that the designations Black or African
feminism were not conceivable as the suffix ‘feminism’ was and still is a foreign
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
concept. On the basis of this understanding, it was, therefore, easier to draw the
conclusion: “No Black African women are ecological feminists.”
Relevant Literature
1. BARCALOW, E. [Moral Philosophy: Theory and Issues], 1994.
Wardsworth Publishing Company: Belmont. Paperback.
2. COLLINS, P. H. “What is in a Name? Womanism, Black Feminism and
Beyond,” [The Black Scholar], pp9-17, Winter/Spring 1996. Vol 1. No
26. Paperback.
3. COPI, I.M. [Introduction to Logic], 1994. Prentice Hall: Eaglewood
Cliffs, New Jersey. Paperback.
4. LADNER, J. “Tomorrow’s tomorrow: The Black Woman.” [Africana
Womanism: Reclaiming Ourselves, C.H Weems, Ed.], 1993. Bedford
Publishers: Michigan. Paperback.
5. MANGENA, F and MUHWATI, I. “Kelland on Rape and
Objectification: An Africana Feminist Response,” 2013. Unpublished
article.
6. ______. “Towards a Hunhu/Ubuntu Dialogical Moral Theory,” [Journal
of the South African Society for Greek Philosophy and the Humanities],
pp1-17, December 2012. Vol 13. No 2. Paperback.
7. ______. “Teaching African Feminist Ethics in the Era of HIV and AIDS:
A University of Zimbabwe Study,” [BOLESWA: Journal of Theology,
Religion and Philosophy], pp117-133, December 2011. Vol 3. No 3.
Paperback.
8. MAPPES, T.A and ZEMBATY, J. S. [Social Ethics: Morality and Social
Policy], 1997. McGraw-Hill: New York. Paperback.
9. STEADY, F.C. “The Black Woman Cross-Culturally,” [Africana
Womanism: Reclaiming Ourselves, C.H Weems, Ed.], 1993. Bedford
Publishers: Michigan. Paperback.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
10. WARREN, K. “The Power and Promise of Ecological Feminism,”
[Ethics: Theory and Contemporary Issues, B Mackinnon, Ed.], 1998.
Wadsworth Publishing Company: Belmont. Paperback.
11. WEEMS, C.H. “Nomo/Self-Naming, Self-Definition and the History of
Africana Womanism,” [Contemporary Africana: Theory, Thought and
Action, C.H Weems, Ed.], 2007. Africa World Press: Trenton.
Paperback.
12. _______. [Africana Womanism: Reclaiming Ourselves], 1993. Bedford
Publishers: Michigan. Paperback.
13. WHITE, L. “The Historical Roots of our Ecological Crisis,” N.P., March
1967. Retrieved 10 July 2013. Web.
Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and Religions
BOOK REVIEW
AN AMAZING PIECE OF COMPARATIVE PHILOSOPHY1
Sophie Bosede Oluwole: Socrates and Orunmila. Two Patron Saints of Classical
Philosophy.
Lagos: Ark Publishers 2014, 224 p.
Reviewer: Prof. Heinz KIMMERLE
Erasmus University Rotterdam
Netherlands, Emeritus
With this book, the debate about African philosophy and the understanding of
what African philosophy is about are raised to a new level. S.B. Oluwole has
worked already for a long time to make clear what is specifically African in
African philosophy. From a great number of publications I just mention her
book: [Witchcraft, Reincarnation and the God-Head: Issues in African
Philosophy], 1991. Excel Publications: Ikeja. In this connection she has drawn
special attention to the problem of [Philosophy and Oral Tradition], 1999. Ark
Publishers: Lagos. She uses frequently and is very familiar with the Ifa Literary
Corpus, an extensive text of Yoruba oral tradition, of which big parts have been
published in print and also translated into English by Wande Abimbola. The
main chapters of this text can be found in the volume, edited by Abimbola:
[Sixteen Great Poems of Ifa], 1975. UNESCO: Paris.
In order to understand what is groundbreaking and new in the
comparison of Socrates and Orunmila, one has to realize that Orunmila and the
other figures of the Ifa Literary Corpus are not gods in the Western meaning of
the word. They are not just mythological figures, as are the gods on Mount
Olympus in the Greek tradition. More specifically it is wrong to speak of
Orunmila as the “God of wisdom.” Oluwole teaches us: These figures are called
Orisa; they are historical human beings who have been “revered only after death”
and “deified” because of their special contribution to philosophy, political
science, knowledge of agrarian production, building of cities, warfare, etc. (see
page xiii). Oluwole’s extensive research into Socrates and Orunmila shows that
there are amazing similarities in their life and work. Both lived around 500 BCE
1
This review first appeared in the journal [Confluence: Online Journal of World
Philosophies], pp221-223, 2014. Vol 1. Web. It is reprinted here by the kind
permission of the reviewer, publisher and the management board of Confluence,
Germany. The original publisher of this review is hereby acknowledged.
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
as the sons of stone masons. Their faces look alike to a great extent. They had
about ten or sixteen disciples to whom they preached virtue as the ideal of the
good life. They heavily criticized those who claimed to possess absolute
knowledge. They lived in centers of intellectual and social life, Athens in ancient
Greece and Ile-Ife in Yoruba-land respectively. Both left behind no written work
(22-24).
It is true for Socrates and Orunmila that we know about them from
secondary sources. There is not an objective report about who they were and
what they taught. Of course, we rely heavily on Plato in trying to find out who
Socrates was. But Plato wrote his famous Dialogues about thirty years after the
death of Socrates. And we have quite different information from Xenophon,
Aristophanes, and Diogenes Laertius about the person and the teachings of
Socrates. From these sources we come to a certain general picture. In this sense
also Gernot Böhme speaks of Der Typ Sokrates (Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp, 1988).
With regard to the person and teachings of Orunmila there are also quite different
sources, which in part have a legendary character. Thus it remains unclear “who
really was Socrates” as well as “Orunmila” (pp8-12 and 19-21).
Oluwole confronts “The Fictitious Socrates,” “The Corporate Socrates,”
and “The Historical Socrates” with “The Mythical Orunmila,” “The Corporate
Orunmila,” and “The Historical Orunmila.” Because there is also a fictitious
picture of Socrates, especially in the work of Aristophanes, corresponding to the
mythical picture of Orunmila in the Ifa corpus, both are comparable. A detailed
comparison of the theoretical “views and ideas” of Socrates and Orunmila about
“The Nature of Reality,” “The Nature of Truth and Wisdom,” “The Limits of
Knowledge and Wisdom,” “The Good and the Bad,” “Political Rights,” “The
Rights of Women” and other topics makes clear that here two philosophies of
equal standard are under discussion. And it is obvious that both argue critically
and reasonably. Their argumentation meets rigorous standards. They deny that
absolute knowledge is possible. “For them, such wisdom belongs to God” (57).
What is said about Orunmila and what Orunmila “is said to have said”
proves that he developed a philosophy within traditional African thought, which
is in no way less critical or rigorous than that of Socrates. Even the most
advanced principles of “Particle Physics which contains algebra and
mathematics” are already applied in the “scientific and mathematical system” of
the structure of the Ifa corpus (79).
From this point of view, Oluwole can not only reject European-Western
positions, which deny the existence of critical and scientific philosophy in
traditional Africa, but also the ideas of many African scholars, who do not give
the full rank of rationality and scientific spirit to traditional African thinkers. She
refers to Kwasi Wiredu, Kwame Gyekye, Gerald Joseph Wanjohi, Peter O.
Bodunrin, and others. Most characteristically wrong is the view articulated by
Vol. 3 No. 2
July – December, 2014
Léopold Sédar Senghor and the Negritude movement. When the latter contrast
the superior position of the West in the field of rational thought with a superior
position of Africa in the field of emotion, they imply that Africans are less
rational (75). J.A.I. Bewaji, who has been teaching at different Nigerian
universities, has delivered a “Critical Analysis of the Philosophical Status of
Yoruba Ifa Corpus.” This results, however, in complete “confusion.” Oluwole
summarizes: Bewaji admits that this text-corpus “is not lacking in a high degree
of ‘abstract reasoning,”’ but at the same time he insists, “that it does not deal
with ‘abstract entities,’ ‘concepts,’ and ‘terms,’ all of which are abstract
reasoning” (90).
In a final conclusion Oluwole clarifies how Socrates, the “Patron Saint”
of classical Western philosophy, makes binary distinctions in the sense of “binary
oppositions.” The binary distinctions of Orunmila, the “Patron Saint” of classical
African philosophy, on the other hand, are “binary complementarity.”2 The way
of thought which is expressed in the idea of complementarity is identified as the
specific contribution of African philosophy to world philosophy. That “the other”
is the necessary condition for my own existence as a human being leads to the
idea of universal brotherhood. The same conception can also be found in the term
“ubuntu” as a ground-word of African philosophy. Mogobe Ramose from the
University of South Africa has developed [African Philosophy Through Ubuntu],
2002. Mond Books: Harare. Oluwole appropriates the “Bantu-sayings” to which
Ramose refers as expressing the core of ubuntu and of binary complementarity. I
quote here only Ramose’s interpretation of the first of these sayings: “Umuntu
ngumuntu ngabantu. To be a human being is to affirm one’s humanity by
recognizing the humanity of others, and on that basis, establish humane
relationship with them” (157). It is necessary to reread Oluwole’s and Ramose’s
books to understand better what is African in African philosophy.
2
The term “Patron Saint” instead of “Baba Ifa” for Orunmila and “Father of
Greek Wisdom” for Socrates is chosen in accordance with the practice in the
“early Christian Church” by which “prominent philosophers […] were later
canonized as saints,” and more particularly with the suggestion of Erasmus to
include “Santa Socrates, Ora pro nobis […] in the liturgy of the Catholic
Church” (xiv).